|
STUDY GUIDE FOR THE FINAL PAPER TOPIC
These notes are intended to help you think about ways of tackling
the question for the final paper topic in INTRO TO PHILOSOPHY (PHIL 1A). The notes are not intended
to
answer the question or, necessarily, to settle one or another
controversial
issue touched upon by the question posed by the examples of The Shallow Pond and The Envelope, but to function, rather, as a
guide
through a maze of quite complicated issues. You will find some notes
to be
helpful, nonetheless, if only as a focusing device and to help you to
decide
what route to take through the mass of possible moves you mgiht
make. You
should feel free to circumscribe your answer to the question, to
concentrate on
certain issues, presumably the ones you believe are the most
germane, the
most important, to the exclusion of others. Thus, some notes that
follow may
be of little interest to you. Here quickly (once again) is the question posed for the final exam.
"Consider the following:
The Shallow Pond
The path from John's dorm room passes a shallow ornamental pond near the center of the campus. On his way to the Philosophy class, John notices that a small child has fallen in and is in danger of drowning. If John wades in and pulls the child out, it will mean getting his clothes wet and muddy and either missing the Philosophy class or delaying it until he can find something clean and dry to wear. He is also wearing a brand new pair of Gucci shoes which he is "breaking in" for the first time. Assume that it is evident from the circumstances that there is no time for John to take his shoes off if he has any hope of saving the child and that John himself can "see" that this is so. John's shoes will become wet and be ruined beyond repair. To replace the shoes will cost him $100. If John passes by the child, then, while he'll make the Philosophy class on time, the child will die straightaway. John heads straight for the Philosophy class and, as expected, the child dies.
Has John behaved badly? What do you think? What is your
immediate, intuitive
moral judgment about John's behavior?
Many think that if a person is walking past a shallow pond and sees a child drowning in it, he or she ought to wade in and pull the child out. If that means getting one's clothes muddy and one's shoes wet, even if it means having to pay a sizeable cleaning bill or having to purchase a new pair of shoes, this is insignificant set against the death of the child which is presumably a very, very bad thing.
And not unsurprisingly, it so happens that almost everyone's intuitive moral judgment is that were that person to pass by, that person's conduct would be abominable.
This case and cases like it, Peter Singer claims, illustrate the intuitive appeal of the following moral principle: "if it is in our power to prevent something bad from happening, without thereby sacrificing something of comparable moral importance, we ought, morally, to do it." In the case of the Shallow Pond, this would appear to be sage moral advice.. If muddying his clothes and getting his "new" shoes wet, saves the life of an innocent child, then it is time for John to send the Cleaners and the Shoe Store some business.
But now Peter Singer also claims that this example shows we have a serious moral obligation to relieve world hunger. But how can this be? Does this case reflect a strong obligation to aid that's quite general? Many think that our intuitive moral responses to examples like the case of the Shallow Pond do not reflect anything very general at all? But now consider the following:
The Envelope
In your mailbox, there's something from (the U.S. Committee for) UNICEF. It's a letter appealing to you to contribute $100 of your own money. After reading it through, you correctly conclude that, unless you soon send in a check for $100, then, instead of each living many more years, over thirty children will soon die of starvation. But, you throw the material in your wastebasket, including the convenient return envelope provided. You send nothing, and, instead of living many years, over thirty more children soon die than would have lived had you sent in the requested $100.
According to Singer, you ought to have sent the money and it was "wrong" for you not to have done so," but almost everyone reacts to this example that your conduct wasn't wrong at all.
Because giving money is regarded as an act of charity, it is not thought that there is anything wrong with not giving. The charitable [person] may be praised, but a [person] who is not charitable is not condemned for failing to give. People do not feel in any way ashamed or guilty about spending money on new clothes or a new car instead of giving it,, in this case, to UNICEF.
And yet Singer believes "this way of looking at the matter cannot be justified."
What do you think? Is it wrong for John to fail to aid the drowning child in the first case, but not wrong for you to fail to prevent thirty children from dying in the second?
If so, what is the moral difference between the two cases?
Drawing on your own most reflective and considered opinion, what is the moral difference (if any) between the two situations that explains the moral judgments of John's conduct in the first case and your conduct in the second case.
One difference, of course, is that the first case involves a pond and a drowning, both of which are absent from the second case. But this surely is not a significant "moral" difference! And the second case involves the postal system, but not the first. But this difference can't make a moral difference, no?
No doubt there may be any number of differences between the two cases, psychological, cultural, and geographical that help to explain people's differing responses to the two cases, but are any of these differences moral differences?
What are the significant moral differences, if any, between the two cases that might help to justify the different judgments of John's and your own conduct?
Or to put the matter another way what might morally ground a negative judgment of John's behavior in the first case and a favorable judgment of your own behavior in the second?
So there you have it once again: the question.
Today I also handed out a preliminary list that
purported to
identify a number of differences between the two cases that some
people have
believed explain our different judgments (not necessarily in the two
cases
before you, but in cases like them) of John's conduct in the case of
"The
Shallow Pond" and your conduct in the case of "The Envelope." The
big
question is, of course, are any of these differences moral differences?
Here once again is that list. It is not intended by any means to be exhaustive. And there are certainly other questions to raise as well as to focus upon in drafting a response to these two cases, the case of the shallow pond and the case of the envelope.
(1) Physical
Proximity
(2) Social
Proximity
(3) Informational
Directness
(4) Experiential
Impact
(5) Unique Potential
Savior
(6) A Single Individual
Saved vs. a Multitude in Need of Saving
(7) Leaving
it to the Government
(8) The Continuing
Mess
(9) Emergencies vs.
Chronic Horrors
(10) Urgency
(11) Causally Focused
vs. Causally Amorphous Aid
(12) Providing a
Service vs. Sending Money
(13) Knowing
Whom You Are Saving vs. Saving Strangers
(14) Taking Care of Our
Own
(15) Overpopulation and
the Ethics of Triage
(16) Helping and
Being Done With It vs. Helping and Helping and
Helping
(17) A
Reasonable Demand vs. Too High a Standard
(18) Saving
vs. Helping to Prevent
(19) Property Rights
Before turning to say a word or two more about each of these
considerations,
(1) through (20), to which a person might appeal to justify and/or
excuse
coming to the aid of the child in need in the first case but not coming
to the
aid of the thirty children in the second, it may make sense to
addresss a few
general concerns (I through VII):
I. In the Case of "The
Envelope" I Am Asked To Save (Prevent)
Thirty
Children from Dying. Surely World Hunger Affects Many People,
Young and
Old Alike: Why Are Children Being Singled Out for My Attention and
Concern?
II. How Can My $100
Keep Thirty Children from Dying? Can You
Break
It Down for Me?
III. It is
Sometimes Said That Morality Itself is Rational, But
What Does
That Mean? For Instance, Henry Shue Says "Basic Rights" Are,
Among Other
Things, "Rational Demands." Should I Worry About Whether My
Sense
That I Should Save the Child from Drowning is Rational or Not? And
What
About "Truth"? Are Moral Judgments True and Objective? And
What if
They are Not? Won't All Hell Break Loose? Aren't We Free Then to
Do as
We Darn Well Please?
IV. I Am Not Quite
Certain How My Moral Intuitions Are
Supposed to
Fit Into All This? Should I Trust My "Moral Intuitions" or Do I Have
Reason
to be Suspicious?
V. The Case of The
Envelope Suggests That If I Send $100 to
UNICEF,
Thirty Less Children Will Die, But There May be Other Ways of
Preventing
Children from Dying That Are Even More Effective Than Sending
Money to
UNICEF. Is This an Excuse or Reason Not to Give?
VI. Peter Singer's
Argument: Consequences, Rights, and
Obligations
VII. Is Singer's Argument
Deceptive?
back to top
I. In the Case of "The Envelope" I Am Asked To Save (Prevent)
Thirty
Children from Dying. Surely World Hunger Affects Many People,
Young and
Old Alike: Why Are Children Being Singled Out for My Attention and
Concern?
"Children are the real victims of world hunger: at least 70% of the
malnourished people of the world are children. By best estimates
forty
thousand children a day die of starvation (Food and Agricultural
Organization (FAO) 1992a: World Food Supplies and Prevalence
of
Chronic Undernutrition in Developing Regions as Assessed in
1992.
Rome: FAO Press: 5). Children do not have the ability to forage for
themselves, and their nutritional needs are exceptionally high. Hence,
they
are unable to survive for long on their own, especially in lean times.
Moreover, they are especially susceptible to diseases and conditions
which are
the staple of undernourished people: simple infections and simple
diarrhea
(United Nations Children's Fund (UNICEF) 1993: The State of
the
World's Children 1993. Oxford: Oxford University Press: 22).
Unless
others provide adequate food, water, and care, children will suffer
and die
(World Health Organization (WHO) 1974: Health Statistics
Report. Geneva: World Health Organization: 677, 679). This fact
must
frame any moral discussions of the problem.
"And so it does at least pre-reflectively. When most of us first see
pictures of
seriously undernourished children, we want to help them, we have a
sense of
responsibility to them, we feel sympathy toward them (Hume, D.
1978: A
Treatise of Human Nature, L.A. Selby-Bigge (ed.). Oxford: Oxford
University Press: 368-71). Even those who think we needn't or
shouldn't help
the starving take this initial response seriously: they go to great
pains to show
that this sympathetic response should be constrained. They typically
claim
that assisting the hungry will demand too much of us, or that
assistance
would be useless and probably detrimental. An effort is, therefore,
made to
show that this sympathetic reaction is morally inappropriate, not
that it does
not exist.
"Our initial sense of responsibility to the starving and malnourished
children
of the world is intricately tied to their being paradigmatically
vulnerable and
innocent. They are paradigmatically vulnerable because they do not
have the
wherewithal to care for themselves; they must rely on others to care
for them.
All children are directly dependent on their parents or guardians,
while
children whose parents cannot provide them food -- either because
of famine
or economic arrangements - are also indirectly dependent on others:
relief
agencies or (their own or foreign) governments. Children are
paradigmatically innocent since they are neither causally nor morally
responsible for their plight. They did not cause drought, parched
land, soil
erosion, and over-population; nor are they responsible for social,
political,
and economic arrangements which make it more difficult for their
parents to
obtain food. If anyone were ever an innocent victim, the children
who suffer
and die from hunger are.
"Infants are especially vulnerable. They temporarily lack the
capacities which
would empower them to acquire the necessities of life. Thus, they
are
completely dependent on others for sustenance. This partly explains
our urge
to help infants in need. James Q. Wilson claims that our instinctive
reaction
to the cry of a newborn child is demonstrated quite early in life.
"'As early as ten months of age, toddlers react visibly to signs of
distress in
others, often becoming agitated; when they are one and a half years
old they
seek to do something to alleviate the other's distress; by the time
they are two
years old they verbally sympathize . . . and look for help' (Wilson, J.
1993:
The Moral Sense. New York: The Free Press: 139-40).
"Although this response may be partly explained by early training,
available
evidence suggests that humans have an 'innate sensitivity to the
feelings of
others' (Wilson 1993: 140). Indeed, Hans Jonas claims the parent-
child
relationship is the 'archetype of responsibility,' where the cry of the
newborn
baby is an ontic imperative 'in which the plain factual "is" evidently
coincides with an "ought"' (Jonas, H. 1984: The Imperative of
Responsibility.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press: 30).
- Hugh LaFolette & Larry May, "Suffer the Children" in World
Hunger
and Morality. Ed. William Aiken and Hugh LaFolette. Prentice
Hall:
Princeton, New Jersey, 1998.
Some useful links:
"
Children and Hunger"
Bread Basket of the World Institute International Facts on Hunger and Poverty
More than 840 million people in the world are malnourished-799 million of them are from the developing world. More than 153 million of them are under the age of five. Six million children under the age of five die every year as a result of hunger. .
Save the
Children. Documents the
neglect of chldren's interests in development planning and offers
alternatives.
Children in Need

back to top
II. How Can My $100 Keep Thirty Children from Dying? Can You
Break
It Down for Me?
"Each year millions of children die from an easy to beat disease, from
malnutrition, and from bad drinking water. Among these children,
about 3
million die from dehydrating diarrhea. As UNICEF has made clear to
millions of us, with a packet of oral rehydration salts that costs about
15 cents,
a child can be saved from dying soon.
"By sending checks earmarked for Oral Rehydration Therapy, or ORT,
to the
U.S Committee for UNICEF, we can help save many of these children.
Here's
the full mailing address:
United States
Committee for UNICEF
United Nations Children's
Fund
333 East 38th Street
New York, NY 10016
Now, you can write that address on an
envelope
well prepared for mailing. And, in it, you can place a $100 check
made out
to the U.S Committee for UNICEF along with a note that's easy
to
write:
WHERE IT WILL HELP THE MOST, USE
THE ENCLOSED
FUNDS FOR ORT.
So, as is reasonable to believe, you can
easily
mean a big difference for vulnerable children.
"Toward realistically thinking about the matter, I have used a figure
far
greater than just 15 cents per child saved: Not only does the U.S.
Committee
have overhead costs, but so does UNICEF itself; and,
there's the cost
of
transporting the packets, and so on. Further, to live even just one
more year,
many children may need several saving interventions and, so,
several
packets. And, quite a few of those saved will die shortly thereafter,
anyway,
from some sadly common Third World cause. So, to be more realistic
about
what counts most, let's multiply the cost of the packet by 10, or,
better, by 20!
"Forgetting one more Third World youngster to escape death and live
a
reasonably long life, $3 is a more realistic figure than 15 cents and,
for present
purposes, it will serve as well as any. Truth to tell, in the light of
searching
empirical investigation, even this higher figure might prove too low.
But, as
nothing of moral import will turn on the matter, we can postpone a
hard
look at the actual cost.
"With this $3 figure in mind, we do well to entertain this proposition:
If
you'd contributed $100 to one of UNICEF's most
efficient life-saving
programs a couple of months ago, this month there'd be over thirty
fewer
children who, instead of painfully dying soon, would live reasonably
long
lives. Nothing here's special to the months just mentioned; similar
thoughts
hold for most your adult life, or from the time your allowance was
big
enough for you to send so much as $100 to UNICEF. And, more
important,
unless we change our behavior, similar thoughts will hold for our
future."
(Much about the causes of childhood death, and about the
interventions that
can nullify these causes, is systematically presented in James P.
Grant's
The State of the World's Children 1993, published for UNICEF
by the
Oxford University Press in 1993. And this information can be cross-
checked
against the (somewhat independent) material in the more massive
World
Development Report 1993, published for the World Bank by the
OUP in
1993. from Peter Unger, "Living and Letting Die." Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996.
Man and Ox Plow, Bangladesh

back to top
III. It is Sometimes Said That Morality Itself is Rational, But
What Does
That Mean? For Instance, Henry Shue Says "Basic Rights" Are,
Among Other
Things, "Rational Demands." Should I Worry About Whether My
Sense
That I Should Save the Child from Drowning is Rational or Not? And
What
About "Truth"? Are Moral Judgments True and Objective? And
What if
They are Not? Won't All Hell Break Loose? Aren't We Free Then to
Do as
We Darn Well Please?
"It's useful to put aside several large matters that, in moments of
confusion,
might be thought greatly to affect an answer to the Final Paper Topic,
but on
closer examination really do not affect the way we might answer the
question
one way or the other. By focusing on two of the very largest of those
matters,
the relationship between morality and rationality and morality and
truth (or
objectivity), I'll try to show how usefully and safely, this may be
done.
"The first concerns the relation between morality and rationality.
For
millennia, philosophers have been concerned to show a strong
connection
between these two normative conceptions. In some instances, their
belief has
been that, unless morality has the backing of rationality, reasonable
people,
like you and me, won't engage in morally decent behavior. But, since
there's
nothing to this thought, I needn't here inquire into the relation
between
morality and rationality.
"Consider the following case, a case closely based on one from James
Rachels:
The Shallow Pond Revisited
You and your four-year-old cousin, Sylvie, a distant relation whom
you've
previously seen only twice, are the only heirs of a bachelor uncle,
very old
and very rich, to whom you're both related. Now, the old man has
only a few
months left. And, as his will states, if both of you are alive when he
dies,
then you'll inherit only one million dollars and your cousin Sylvie, to
whom
the uncle's much more closely related, will inherit fully nine; but, if
the order
of deaths is first your cousin Sylvie, and then your uncle, you'll
inherit all of
ten million dollars. Right now, you see that it's this cousin Sylvie of
yours
who, even as she's the only other person anywhere about, is on the
verge of
drowning in the shallow ornamental pond. As it happens, you can
easily
arrange for things to look like you were then elsewhere, at the
Human Rights
Class or grabbing something to eat in USDAN; so, if you let the child
drown,
you can get away with it completely. And, since you'd take a drug
that would
leave you with no memories of the incident at all, you'll never feel
even the
slightest guilt. So, in a short time, you'll be able to enjoy ten million
dollars,
not just a measly million.
"As is very clear, your letting the child drown is extremely immoral
behavior.
But, it might be asked, is it irrational behavior? Now, some
philosophers will
hold that it's also irrational. By contrast, others will hold that, on at
least one
sense of 'rationality,' your conduct isn't irrational: You care for this
very
distant cousin Sylvie little more than for a perfect stranger; largely
owing to
the 'wonder' drug, there won't be any significantly bad effects on
your life;
and, 'hey, nine million ain't nothing to sneeze at,' and so on.
"For the sake of the exposition, let's suppose that, as a recent number
of
arguments from rational choice theory and cost-benefit analysis all
conspire
to show, the second group of philosophers is completely correct. On
the
understanding of rational behavior put forward by this second group,
your
saving the child must be highly irrational. For good measure, let's
suppose, too, that you've become quite convinced of this yourself.
With
these strong suppositions firmly in mind, how many of us would let
our
four-year old cousin Sylvie drown?
"Very few will be even so much as strongly disposed to behave in
such an
immoral manner and fewer still would actually do it. So, fas far as
being a
potent guide for our conduct, morality certainly doesn't need any
help from
whatever authority we may accord to rationality. For the Final Paper
Topic,
it's quite enough to learn a lot about which conduct is really morally
all right
and, in contrast, which is immoral. If the former also has
rationality's
backing, that's fine; but, if not, it's no big deal.
"Properly placing to the side the very interesting question of how
rationality
relates to morality, I'll turn to the equally interesting question of
how truth
relates to morality. Now, various philosophers have been concerned
to show
that there are many significant moral truths and that, far from
reducible to
even the wisest people's most basic moral commitments, they're as
fully
objective as any truths. Again, given the purpose and significance of
the
question for the final, it's a distracting digression to investigate this
issue.
"Why do objectivists offer arguments for our meta-ethical positions?
Ranging from sheer intellectual impulses to religious convictions, the
motivation behind these endeavors is very varied. But, it's just this
worrisome one that perhaps stands in need of discussion here and
now:
What would happen if we believed there weren't any meaningful
moral
truths; wouldn't all hell break loose? Rather than feeling constrained
by our
deepest moral commitments, won't even decent folks like you and
me be free
to do whatever we please, or whatever is to our advantage? For, if
our moral
values don't point to some reality beyond themselves, then there's
nothing
to adhere any more than our most selfish desires. And, then, too,
there won't
be much point to trying to figure out what our moral values may be
trying to
tell us any more than trying to figure our preferences for Super
Fudge Chunk
or Cherry Garcia.
"Though those thoughts have a certain appeal, they're deeply
confused.
Recall the Rival Heirs and, this time, suppose you've come to think
there
aren't any objective moral truths. Will that free you up to let your
four-year
old cousin Sylvie drown? Not a chance. None of this is to deny the
philosophical importance of investigating the relations between
morality and
truth or morality and rationality; it's just to say that, whatever holds
for these
metaphysical matters, investigating our moral values directly may
lead us to
engage in more decent behavior, quite apart from the answers we
may give to
these larger issues of moralitys rationality and truth." from Peter Unger, "Living and Letting Die." Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996.
Woman at Rice Mill, Bangladesh

back to top
IV. I Am Not Quite Certain How My Moral Intuitions Are
Supposed to
Fit Into All This? Should I Trust My "Moral Intuitions" or Do I Have
Reason
to be Suspicious?
Why might we be suspicious about our immediate, moral intuitions.
Well,
one reason to be suspicious is that some moral intutions that some
people
have had about certain forms of conduct in the past, are not the same
as the
intuitions that people have today.
Consider the accepted assessments of two famous Virginian founders
of the
United States, George Washington and Thomas Jefferson. They're
pretty
nearly as positive as Jefferson's judgments of Washington:
'In war we have produced a Washington, whose memory will be
adored while liberty shall have votaries, whose name will triumph
over time, and will in future ages assume its just station among the
most celebrated worthies of the world. . . ' (from Jefferson's 'Notes on
the State of Virginia,' as included in Merrill D. Peterson, ed.,
Thomas Jefferson: Writings, The Library of America, 1984,
p.190. Jefferson's 'Notes' were originally published in England in
1787)
He was, indeed, in every sense of the words, a wise, a good and a
great
man. . . His heart was not warm in its affections; but he exactly
calculated every man's value, and gave him a solid esteem
proportioned to it....On the whole, his character was, in its mass,
perfect, in nothing bad, in few points indifferent; and it may truly be
said, that never did nature and fortune combine more perfectly to
make a man great, and to place him in the same constellation with
whatever worthies have merited from man an everlasting
remembrance. . . (Jefferson's letter of January 2, 1814 to Dr. Walter
Jones; see page 1319 of Thomas Jefferson: Writings)
So, we think that Washington was, at the very least, quite a good
man. And,
even as we also greatly admire Jefferson, we believe that, overall,
their
conduct was good.
But, a little hard thought makes the lofty assessments puzzling:
During all
their years of maturity, they had slaves and, in the bargain, they
lived
lavishly. Now, as historians indicate, it wasn't impossible for them to
free
their slaves and live less lavishly. About Washington's last two years,
Alden
writes:
He now owned 277 slaves, far more than could be usefully employed
at Mount Vernon. It was possible for him, by selling many that he
did
not need, both to secure cash and to reduce his expenses, but he
could
not bring himself to resort to such a sale, certain to bring
unhappiness
to the slaves. He even considered the possibility of developing
another plantation where the blacks not needed at Mount Vernon
could be located. He also was concerned with arrangements for
property when he should die. In the late summer of 1798 he had
been
seriously ill with a fever and had lost twenty pounds. He had rapidly
regained weight and was to all appearances in very good health.
Nevertheless, he was conscious that his death would come at no
distant time. He drew up his will. Martha was to enjoy the use of the
bulk of his estate. After her death Bushrod Washington was to have
Mount Vernon, and the remainder of the estate except for special
bequests was to be divided among his relatives and those of Martha,
with one most important exception. He was determined to free his
slaves. His personal servant, Billy Lee, was to be freed immediately
upon Washington's death. His blacks and those belonging to Martha
had intermarried, and he could not legally set loose her blacks during
her lifetime. Accordingly, he arranged for all of their slaves to be
freed at her death. His executors must provide for the aged blacks,
and
the young were to be supported and taught to read and write. He
stipulated that certain shares of stock should be used to help finance
schools . . . (John R. Alden, George Washington, Baton Rouge
and London: Louisiana State University Press, 1984, pp. 302-303)
But, of course, much of that conduct is very questionable. Why didn't
Washington free some of his solely owned slaves well before his
death, like
Billy Lee, for one? Apparently, by selling some few stocks, our first
President
could have provided well for them. Evidently, there's no morally
satisfactory
answer. And, even if George had to convince Martha by threatening
her,
with divorce or worse, why didn't he see to it that, long before either
died, all
their slaves were freed and supported? Again, no very decent
answer.
In various ways, Jefferson's life differed from Washington's, but not
in any
ways that excuse him. For, he also could have freed his slaves
without any
serious suffering. To be sure, had either done that, he wouldn't have
enjoyed
such a lavish Virginian life. But, morally, so what? Until their deaths,
both
freely remained slaveholders. When that fact's combined with our
positive
assessments, there's this puzzle about the Old Virginians: How can
someone
who keeps behaving like that, year after year, be a decent person, or
be
someone whose total behavior is even all right? Apparently, in our
moral
assessments, there's a questionable double-standard at work: For
those
Virginians, slaveholding won't disqualify their total conduct from
having
high moral status. But, for us, no such assessment's available.
That's puzzling; but, the puzzle can instruct. So, next, let's note some
historical differences. By contrast with our society today, in old
Virginia
things were like this: First, it was a common practice to hold slaves.
Second,
as far as many engaged in the practice were concerned slaveholding
wasn't a
morally terrible thing. Third, through interaction with folks who
behaved
and thought like they did, for Old Virginians social pressure made it
psychologically very hard to choose to become slaveless.
On first reflection many think those three differences do much to
explain the
puzzling disparity. While that thought's initially plausible, it's very
misleading. To show how it's misleading, it's helpful look at a puzzle
that's
an expansion of the puzzle of the Old Virginians, the Puzzle of the
Imaginary
Australians. After a short Historical Preamble, I'll do some Stage
Setting, and,
then, we'll confront the Puzzle of the Imaginary Australians itself.
Historical Preamble: When slavery prevailed in Virginia, it was also
prevalent even in various distant parts of the world. In Brazil, for
example, it
continued for decades after it ended in the South of the United
States. In
Volume 2 of The World Book Encyclopedia, the 1988 edition,
for
example, there's an article "Brazil," by J. H. Galloway of the University
of
Toronto. He ends the section on "The Age of Pedro II," with these
words: 'In
1888, a law abolished slavery in Brazil and freed about 750,000
slaves. Most of
them had worked on plantations, and Brazil's powerful slaveowners
became
angry at Pedro when they were not paid for their slaves. In 1889,
Brazilian
military officers supported by the plantation owners forced Pedro to
give up
his throne. He died in Paris two years later. In 1922, his body was
brought back
to Brazil. Brazilians still honor Pedro II as a national hero.' By
contrast, in still
other parts of the world, like Australia, there never was any slavery.
According to the article "Australia" in same Encyclopedia, Australia's
white
settlers treated her Aborigines very much as the whites who settled
in what's
now the U.S. treated this country's Native Americans. While very
bad
behavior, that wasn't slaveholding. End of Preamble.
Onto the Stage Setting: Imagine an entire contemporary society
where, year
after year, many still engage in slaveholding. Imagine, too, that this
contemporary society is Peter Singer's native land, Australia. The
Stage is Set.
Suppose the early Australian settlers enslaved the island's
Aborigines and,
even today, many wealthy Australians have slaves working on their
vast
ranches and farms. Still, insofar as it's possible with folks kept as
slaves, these
masters treat them well, providing, for example, better facilities and
accommodations than at all but the finest resorts. Now, among the
very most benevolent masters are one Paul Singer and one Mary
Singer, each
a first cousin of Peter. ( Of course, Peter himself doesn't keep any
slaves and
does all he can to end slavery.) Because they've discussed his views
with him for years, Paul and Mary agree with Peter about all manner
of issues
their behavior might address, except for the matter of slavery. And,
even on
that score, his cousins' beliefs aren't all that different from Peter's.
For, they
believe what, at least at last, Washington and Jefferson believed:
While
slavery's certainly bad, it might not be all that horribly bad. What's
more,
we'll suppose that, apart from their slaveholding, Paul and Mary
conduct
themselves in a way that's even better than the morally good way
Peter
behaves. For example, working extremely hard and living very
modestly,
each year Paul gives almost all of the huge income from his organic
fruit
orchards toward the saving of many children in the Third World, and
toward
lessening other serious suffering. So, what we're supposing amounts
to this:
Apart from slaveholding, Peter Singer's cousins' conduct is much
better than
almost anyone's.
So (now) what's our intuitive assessment of their total behavior? As
most
respond, it's rather bad. But, a couple of questions show this
negative
judgment to be very puzzling: Why do we judge the imaginary
Australians'
conduct negatively, but judge the old Virginians' positively? And,
even if we
can find an explanatorily adequate answer, what adequate moral
justification
can there be for such a disparity?
As for the first question, it's clear there's a lot that needs explaining:
In
regards to the matter of slavery, Paul's and Mary's extremely
benevolent
conduct is at least somewhat better than Washington's and
Jefferson's
behavior. As regards other matters, since the Australians' conduct is
morally
so marvelous, it's also at least somewhat better than the Old
Virginians'. But,
those are all the matters there are! So, the conduct of our imaginary
Australians is better than the behavior of our old Virginians.
When starting to explain, we might first note this: With the old
Virginians,
there were other societies then also heavily involved in slaveholding.
But,
with the imaginary Australians, theirs is the only society where
there's still
slavery. Is that a good way to start? Hardly. Just ponder this apt
enlargement
of the hypothetical example: In addition to Australia's large society,
several
others, like Brazil's, persisted in slavery right up to the present time.
To this
expanded case, mostpeople respond just as negatively.
The Puzzle of the Imaginary Australians accentuates what's
disturbing in the
Puzzle of the Old Virginians. But what's going on in these cases?
Without
telling too long a story, here's one attempt at a short answer:
To begin, it's worth noting that, in our moral judgments, we're
greatly
influenced by 'The Idea of Moral Progress.' With regard to certain
morally
bad forms of behavior, (we have the idea that) humanity has morally
progressed beyond its being even the least bit normal for anyone to
engage in
behavior of those forms. Of course, slaveholding is one of these
morally
surpassed forms. And, much earlier still, we progressed beyond its
being at all
normal to support entertainments where people try to kill each
other, as with
the gladiators of ancient Rome. Here's a suggestion about that Idea's
influence: Once a very bad form of behavior is (taken by us to be)
surpassed,
we'll give negative assessments to the total conduct of those (taken
to be)
engaged in behavior of that form after what's actually (taken to be)
the time of
the surpassing, (unless they break with the form, soon enough, and
then
don't resume such bad behavior). By contrast, when someone's
engagement
in a bygone form is all before that actual time, we're open to giving
his or her
total conduct a positive assessment. It's this pervasive double-faced
tendency
that explains both our strangely disparate responses to many actual
cases, as
with the Puzzle of the Old Virginians, and our strange reactions to
many
hypothetical cases, as with the Puzzle of the Imaginary Australians.
Both to make the suggestion's content clearer and to provide it with
support,
another far-fetched example serves well: For all of the 18th and
much of the
19th century, to entertain themselves and other white folks, certain
Virginian
masters occasionally made one of their slaves fight to the death with
the slave
of another wealthy slaveholder. As we'll suppose, while Washington
took
care never even to so much as attend any such ghastly event,
Jefferson was
one of these "Neo-Roman" practitioners and, as the odds had it, some
of his
slaves were killed in these "backyard spectacles." To this case, we
make the
definite moral response that Washington's total conduct would have
been
good and Jefferson's bad.
Many believe, at least in certain respects, there's been some moral
progress.
And, some of it satisfies 'The Idea of Moral Progress.' But, the
influence of
that 'Idea' is far stronger, perhaps, than it should be: Mainly owing to
that, we
underrate the total conduct of people who, as we suppose, engage in
behavior
of a form that's been surpassed; just so, we underrated Paul's and
Mary's
(hypothetical) total behavior. And, as regards the whole of their
conduct, we
overrate those who, before it was surpassed, did engage in such bad
behavior;
just so, we overrate Washington's and Jefferson's (actual) total
conduct. And,
closely related to both of those distortional tendencies, perhaps a
third
involves us in closely related errors.
Perhaps, right now, we're engaging in conduct that, though it's of
certain
morally horrible forms, is still quite normal behavior. Then, since
these bad
forms haven't been surpassed, we may be overrating our own
behavior.
Now, perhaps our (distant) descendants will make so much moral
progress
that, at some future time, humanity will surpass some of these bad
behavioral forms. But, if 'The Idea of Moral Progress' has much the
same
influence then as now, which we may very well suppose, even they
will
overrate us. Let's pursue that thought.
Here's a form of behavior that, though we're now heavily engaged in
it,
might well be thought terrible by our descendants and, for that
reason, might
be morally surpassed by them: letting distant innocents needlessly
die by, say,
our not sending money to UNICEF. So, even if it never actually
happens, i.e.,
that our descendants come to think this way, we may instructively
suppose
that, centuries hence, humanity's made just such progress as this:
Whenever
well-off folks learn of people in great need, they promptly move to
meet the
need, almost no matter what the financial cost. So, at this late date,
the basic
needs of almost all the world's people will be met almost all the time.
Still,
once in a while, a great natural disaster may befall many folks in
what is, then
as now, one of the world's most dangerous areas, like the cyclone
prone coast
of Bangladesh. Whether through demanding to be taxed more by
their
governments, or through contributing to non-governmental
organizations,
or whatever, very many millions of the world's more fortunate folks
make
sure such beleaguered people don't ever undergo more serious
suffering than
a big cyclone causally necessitates. What's more, should any of these
descendants find themselves facing such preventable suffering as
now
actually obtains, they'd devote almost all their energy, and resources,
toward
lessening the suffering. To do any less would be as unthinkable for
them. say,
as having slaves is unthinkable (now) to us. Finally, in making moral
judgments, they'll be just as affected as we by 'The Idea of Moral
Progress.'
Just as we overrate Washington and Jefferson, cutting them slack in
the
matter of slaveholding, they'll overrate you and me, cutting us slack
in the
matter of allowing children in need to die.
From this discussion, two lessons emerge, one pretty specific, the
other far
more general. Specifically, as we've seen one distortional tendency
evoke
misleading responses, both to hypothetical examples and even to
actual cases,
it won't be surprising to see with regard to a number of
considerations in our
list of (1) through (20) supposed differences between the case of the
Shallow
Pond and the case of The Envelope, the operation of others. More
generally,
this thought puts the whole enterprise of making sense of our
reposnses to
the case of the Shallow Pond and the case of The Envelope in an
appropriately humbling perspective: However much we increase our
awareness of morality, it may hardly ever seem that our currently
very
consequential conduct is even mildly wrong. from Peter Unger, "Living and Letting Die." Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996.
Girls Playing, Guatamala

back to top
V. The Case of The Envelope Suggests That If I Send $100 to
UNICEF,
Thirty Less Children Will Die, But There May be Other Ways of
Preventing
Children from Dying That Are Even More Effective Than Sending
Money to
UNICEF. Is This an
Excuse or Reason Not to Give?
It is true there are many who live in the affluent nations who fear
that their
aid won't do anything more than line the pockets of charitable
organizations.
But we have already addressed this issue to some extent by re-
calculating the
value of the $100 you send to UNICEF, taking into
account that some
of it will
go to administrative costs. But then there is another related worry,
the worry
that the money sent to UNICEF will not solve
the problem of chronic
starvation. More likely we should empower the children's primary
caretakers so they can care and feed their children. But while it is
true that
there are clear links between, say, literacy rates and chronic
malnutrition such
that mothers with higher literacy rates are less likely to have
malnourished
children and so it may appear that one way to begin to "solve" the
problem of
world hunger is by funding programs that improve the overall
literacy of a
people in a given region, it also remains true, right now, that sending
money
to UNICEF will
prevent the deaths of thirty children.
The issue then, however, is whether to send money but to whom it
should be
sent. OXFAM, for one, provides aid to empower people, who live in
countries and regions of the world prone to famine and malnutrition,
to feed
themselves and their children. So if your worry is that your money
may
prevent more deaths in the long run or is likely to be more efffective
if sent to
one organization than another, you should modify the case of The
Envelope
to address this worry, not use it as an excuse to give no money at all.
This
worry is addressed further in the section on Emergencies vs. Chronic
Horrors
below, but if it's a worry that is likely to get in the way of your being
able to
think about the question effectively, you should change the name of
the
organization from UNICEF to OXFAM and
send or fail to send a check
to
OXFAM instead. So to make these considerations a little less abstract,
here are several key links which will enable you to contact Oxfam
Amercia, one of a number of independent organizations around the
world and under the general auspices of Oxfam International:
Oxfam
International
Oxfam America
Oxfam Canada
Oxfoam Community Aid
Abroad, Oxfam in Australia
Oxfam Hong
Kong
Interm-n website
Oxfam in Spain
Oxfam New
Zealand
Oxfam in the Netherlands
Oxfam Quebec
Oxfam
Latina Oxfam Great Britain's
Spanish language Web site for Latin America
Oxfam
(India)
Information and analysis on Oxfam in India
On
The Line Make
the millennium more than just a moment in time with On The
Line: a partnership project of
Oxfam GB, World Wildlife Fund UK and Channel 4 Television
In speaking to this worry about the effectiveness of the aid, your
inability to
figure out which relief agencies are likely to be most effective should
not
determine or cloud your thinking about whether or not you ought to
send
money at all. It's important to emphasize that UNICEF is quite
effective in
doing what it does on behalf of children in need. You could send the
money
to OXFAM, but you should know if you do send money to UNICEF, you
will
prevent children from dying.
In this regard, it may be useful to say something about the regions
where the
easily preventable childhood deaths have been occurring. In each of
the past
30 years, well over 10 million children died from readily
preventable causes.
And, except for a lack of money aimed at doing the job, most of the
deaths
could have been prevented by using any one of many means.
First, there's this well-known fact: Over ninety percent of these
deaths occur
in the countries of the so-called "Third World." By contrast, here's
something much less widely known: Though almost all these needless
deaths
occur in the materially poorest parts of the world, poverty itself is
hardly the
whole story.
For a good case in point, take the poverty-ridden Indian state of
Kerala,
shown in the film 'The Politics of Food.' While per capita income in
this
state of about thirty million is notably lower than in India as a
whole, life
expectancy in Kerala is higher than in any other Indian state. And,
the
childhood mortality rate is much lower than in India as a whole.
Why?
Without telling a long historical story, most of the answer may be put
like
this: In this vibrantly democratic and responsive state, Kerala's
millions have
food security, safe drinking water and very basic health care. By
contrast,
many of the richer Indians don't have their basic needs met, and
don't have
their children's needs met. So, while often a factor, poverty itself
hardly
explains why millions of kids needlessly die each year.
As is well known, many millions of children don't get enough to eat.
These
related truths are less well known: First, for each child that dies in a
famine,
several die from chronic malnutrition. Second, even if she gets over
eighty
percent of the calories needed by a youngster of her age for excellent
health, a
child who regularly gets less than ninety percent is so malnourished
that
she'll have a dangerously inadequate immune system. Third, what
happens
to many such vulnerable children is that, because they are among
the many
millions who haven't been vaccinated against measles, when they get
measles they die from it. So, fourth, each year mere measles still
kills about a
million Third World kids. UNICEF's worldwide
immunization
campaign
has been making great strides against measles for years. So, while
just a few
years ago measles claimed over 1.5 million young lives, in recent
years, it has
claimed about 1 million.
Several means of reducing measles deaths are worth mentioning,
including
these: Semiannually, an underfed child can be given a powerful dose
of
Vitamin A, with capsules costing less than 10 cents. For that year,
this will
improve the child's immune system. So, if she hasn't been
vaccinated,
during this year, she'll be better able to survive measles. What's
more, from
her two capsules, she'll get a big bonus: With her immune system
improved,
this year she'll have a better chance of beating the two diseases that
take far
more young lives than measles claims, pneumonia and diarrhea.
Though usually all that's needed to save a child from pneumonia is
the
administration of antibiotics that cost about 25 cents, pneumonia
now claims
about 3.5 million young lives a year, making it the leading child-
killing
disease. But, let's again focus on measles.
For about $17 a head, UNICEF can vaccinate
children against measles.
On the
positive side, the protection secured lasts a life-time; with no need
for
semiannual renewal, there's no danger of failing to renew protection!
What's more, at the same time each child can be vaccinated for life-
time
protection against five other diseases that, taken together, each year
kill about
another million Third World children: tuberculosis, whooping cough,
diphtheria, tetanus and polio. Perhaps best of all, these vaccinations
will be
part of a world-wide immunization campaign that, over the years, is
making
progress toward eliminating these vaccine-preventable diseases,
much as
smallpox was eliminated only a decade or two ago. Indeed, with no
incidence
in the whole Western Hemisphere since 1991, polio is quite close to
being
eliminated; with good logistical systems in place almost everywhere,
the
campaign's success depends mainly on funding. In 'Polio Isn't Dead
Yet,'
which appeared in The New York Times, June 10, 1995, Hugh
Downs,
the chairman of the U.S. Committee, usefully writes, 'The United
States
spends $270 million on domestic [polio] immunization each year. For
about
half that amount polio could be eliminated worldwide in just five
years,
according to experts from Unicef and the World Health Organization.
If the
disease is wiped off the earth, we would no longer need to immunize
American children and millions of dollars could be diverted to other
pressing
needs.'
Finally, the vast majority of the world's very vulnerable children live
in
lands with UNICEF
programs operating productively, including all 13
developing countries lately ranked, i.e., as of 1992, among the
world's 20 most
populous nations: China, India, Indonesia, Brazil, Pakistan,
Bangladesh,
Nigeria, Mexico, Vietnam, Philippines, Iran, Turkey and Thailand.
Each of
these countries has a well established UNICEF program in
place, and
the
program work wells in large parts of each of these countries. And
this means
that through the likes of UNICEF, it's well
within the power of each of
us, in
the coming months and years, to lessen serious suffering.
For even modestly well-informed persons, these facts do not come as
a big
surprise. All they'll have learned are some particulars pertaining to
what
they've learned long ago: By directing donations toward a worthy
end, well-
off folks can be very effective in lessening serious suffering and loss.
Indeed,
so well accustomed are many of us to this thought that, after hearing
the
presented facts, most of us won't make any notable response. For far
fewer
persons, what's related here will be something completely new. From
many
of them, remarks such as these often evoke a very notable response,
even if a
fleeting one, about how we ought to behave: The thought occurs that
each of
us should contribute (what may well be for us) quite a lot to lessen
early
deaths; indeed, it's seriously wrong not to do so.
But, soon after making such a strict response, the newly aware also
become
well accustomed to the thought about our power. And, then, they
also make
the much more lenient response that almost everyone almost always
makes:
While it's good for us to provide vital aid, it's not even the least bit
wrong to
do nothing to help save distant people from painfully dying soon.
The
prevalence of the lenient response is apparent from so much passive
behavior: Even when unusually good folks are vividly approached to
help
save distant young lives, it's very few who contribute anything. In a
typical
recent year, 1993, the U.S. Committee for UNICEF mailed out,
almost
every
month, informative appeals to over 450,000 potential donors. The
prospects
were folks whose recorded behavior selected them as well above the
national
average in responding to humanitarian appeals. With only a small
overlap
between people in each mailing, during the year over 4 million
"charitable"
Americans were vividly informed about what just a few of their
dollars
would mean. With each mailing, a bit less than 1% donated anything,
a
pattern persisting year after year. from Peter Unger, "Living and Letting Die." Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996.
Which of these two opposite responses gives the more accurate
indication of
what morality requires? Is it really seriously wrong not to do
anything to
lessen distant suffering; or, is it quite all right to do nothing?
Haitian Children, Haiti

back to top
VI. Peter Singer's Argument: Consequences, Rights, and
Obligations
While directly concerned more with famine relief than with the
children's
health issues just highlighted, it was Peter Singer who first thought
to argue,
seriously and systematically, that it's the first response that's on
target. Both
early on and recently, he offers an argument for the proposition that
it's
wrong for us not to lessen distant serious suffering. His argument's
first
premise is this general proposition: 'If we can prevent something
bad
without sacrificing anything of comparable moral significance, we
ought to do
it.'
So that it may help yield his wanted conclusion, Singer has us
understand
this premise in a suitably strong sense, with its consequent, 'we
ought to do
it,' entailing 'it's wrong for us not to do it,' not just 'it's better for us
to do it
than not.'
Singer, too, believes that the general proposition should appeal to
utilitarians
and non-utilitarians alike, 'because,' as he says, 'the injunction to
prevent
what is bad only applies when when nothing comparably significant
is at
stake. Thus, the principle cannot lead to the kinds of actions that
[human
rights activists] strong disapprove: serious violations of individual
[human]
rights.' Again, as he Singer says, if anyone who cares deeply about
human
rights regards 'these violations as comparable in moral significance to
the bad
thing that is to be prevented, they will automatically regard the
principle as
not applying in those cases in which the bad thing can only be
prevented by
violating rights . . .'
Girl Drawing Water, Cambodia

back to top
VII. Is Singer's Argument Deceptive?
Singer acknowledges that the non-controversial appearance of the
principle
'that we ought to prevent what is bad when we can do so without
sacrificing
anything of comparable moral significance is deceptive. If it were
taken
seriously and acted upon, our lives and our world would be
fundamentally
changed. For the principle applies, not just to rare situations in
which one
can save a child from a pond , but to the everyday situations in
which we can
assist those living in absolute poverty. In saying this [Singer]
assumes that
absolute poverty, with its hunger and malnutrition, lack of shelter,
illiteracy,
disease, high infant mortality, and low life expectancy, is a bad thing.
[He]
assumes that it is within the power of the affluent to reduce absolute
poverty,
without sacrificing anything of comparable moral significance. If
these two
assumptions and the principle . . . are correct, we have an obligation
to help
those in absolute poverty that is no less strong than our obligation to
rescue a
drowning child from a shallow pond.' More formally, the argument
Singer
makes looks like this:
First Premise:
'If we can prevent something bad from happening without sacrificing
anything of comparable moral significance, we ought to to do it.'
Second Premise:
'Absolute poverty is wrong.'
Third Premise:
'There is some absolute poverty we can prevent without sacrificing
anything
of comparable moral significance.'
Conclusion:
'We ought to prevent some absolute poverty.'
But if we examine Singer's third premise more closely, it may, on
closer
examination, prove to be less deceptive and controversial than it first
appears.
As Singer says, the third premise 'only claims that some absolute
poverty can
be prevented without the sacrifice of anything of comparable moral
significance. It thus avoids the objection that any aid I can give is
just "drops
in the ocean" for the point is not whether my personal contribution
will
make any noticeable impression on world poverty (of course it
won't) but
whether it will prevent some poverty. This is all the argument needs
to
sustain its conclusion, since the second premise says that any
absolute poverty
is bad, and not merely the total amount of absolute poverty.' So, as
Singer
argues, 'if without sacrifice anything of comparable moral
significance, we can
provide just one family with the means to raise itself out of absolute
poverty,
the third premise is vindicated.'
Singer's talk of an obligation to assist those who are in absolute
poverty can
easily be translated into talk of an obligation to assist children in
need. For
instance, by sending $100 to UNICEF, you need not
think that your
contribution will or must 'make any noticeable impression' on
preventing
childhood deaths in the developing countries, only that it will
prevent thirty
more children from dying.
And this brings us full circle, back to a consideration of the larger
question:
What might morally ground judging John's conduct in the case of the
Shallow Pond negatively, but not judging your conduct in the case of
The
Envelope negatively?
It is certainly true that there are any number of significant
differences
between the two cases. The issue before you, however, is to ask and
answer
for yourself whether any of these differences are moral differences.
It is one
thing to explain our moral intuitions and responses; it is quite
another to
justify them. Do any of the differences enumerated and expanded
upon
below not only explain but also justify our moral judgments of John's
conduct in the one case and your conduct in the other?
Woman Weaver, India

back to top
VIII. The Child That John Could Save from Drowning Was Only a
Few
Feet Away from Him; Whereas the Children in the Envelope Case are
Miles
Away (Physical Proximity)
Now while it is true that we often help those and are more likely to
help
those in need who are physically close to us and while it is hard for
most of us
to stand by and watch a child drown, but many can ignore children
in need
who happen to live half way around the globe in, say, Bangladesh,
the
question is not, as Peter Singer points out, 'what we usually do, but
what we
ought to do, and it is difficult to see any sound moral justification for
the
view that distance . . . makes a crucial diffference to our obligations.'
Or as
Peter Unger says 'unlike many physical forces, the strength of a
moral force
does not diminish with distance.' What do you think? Clearly, the
physical
proximity of the child in the case of the Shallow Pond makes it
psychologically and emotionally more likely that someone
who passes by will come to her aid. But can these factors be
translated into
moral factors? Consider the following:
The Bungalow Compound
Not being truly rich, you own a one-twelfth share in a small
bungalow that's part of a beach resort compound in an exotic but
poor country, say, Haiti. For some time now there's been much
strife in the land, and now it's your month to enjoy the bungalow,
and you happen to be in Haiti on your annual vacation. In your
mailbox, there's an envelope from UNICEF asking for
money to
help save children's lives in the town in Haiti nearest you,
whichever one that is. In your very typical case, quite a few such
needy kids are all within a few blocks of the Bungalow where you
are staying and, just over the compound wall, some are only a few
feet away. As the appeal makes clear, your $100 will mean the
difference between long life and early death for thirty nearby
children. But, of course, each month such appeals are sent to many
bungalows in many Haitian resort compounds. You throw the
material in your wastebasket, including the convenient return
envelope provided, you send nothing, and, instead of living many
years, over thirty more Haitian children soon die than would have
died had you sent in the requested $100.
Putting aside all other factors, such as your contributing to the
Haitian
economy by virtue of the fact that you have a time-sharing
arrangement in
the country and may (even) as a result contribute some tax
revenues, does the
fact that some of the children whose lives your $100 might save live
within a
few feet of the Bungalow Compound make a moral difference in your
judgment of such a person, i.e., a person who sends nothing and so
nearby
children die? No doubt some people might be more likely to
contribute in
this case than in the original case of The Envelope. Some, too, may be
more
likely to feel guilty if they fail to contribute, in part, because they
vacation in
Haiti and, as a result, feel more connected to its citizens. But if you
do not
think it is in the least bit wrong not to contribute in the case of The
Envelope,
why would it suddenly become wrong now (in the case of the
Bungalow
Compound) that the children in need are just 'a few feet away?'
from Peter Unger, "Living and Letting Die." Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996.
Women Processing Grain, Mali

back to top
IX. The Child That John Could Save from Drowning Was, Like
John, an
American; Whereas the Children in the Envelope Case are All
Foreigners
(Social Proximity)
While (again) it may be more likely that John will respond to the
drowning
child more immediately if the child is socially close to him, even this
is far
from obvious. In such a case there may not be much time to
determine the
nationality or ethnicity of the drowning child and no one surely
would
suggest that if John elected to 'do the right thing' and save the child
that were
he to discover, once he had saved her, that she was Bolivian, not
American,
he would throw her back. Putting aside the related issues of
whether, for
instance, we should only be obligated to members of our own family,
surely
the ethnicity or nationality of the child has no moral relevance!
from Peter Unger, "Living and Letting Die." Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996.
Or
does it?
Spices in Marketplace, Somalia

back to top
X. In the Case of the Drowning Child in the Pond John acquires
his
information directly; he "sees" what he needs to do. But in the case
of The
Envelope the information is much more indirect.
How an agent learns of the great need he can help meet may make a
difference in certain cases, but if it does, it usually does so because
the
information that we acquire indirectly is less reliable or we are less
inclined to
be sure if it's true. But in the case of The Envelope you can be quite
certain
what is going to happen if you do not contribute to UNICEF. And if
this is,
isn't it also true that the fact that you acquire the information
directly morally
insignificant? from Peter Unger, "Living and Letting Die." Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996.
Man with Bike, Cambodia

back to top
XI. In the Case of the Drowning Child in the Pond John acquires
his
information directly; he "sees" what he needs to do. But in the case
of The
Envelope the information is much more indirect.
Experiential impact often goes along with informative directness: In
the case
of the Drowning Child, both the needy child himself and the condition
of her
great need entered into John's own experience. But, that's not so in
the
Envelope. About this difference, common sense is clear: While the
need may
seem more pschologically compelling in the case of the Shallow Pond
than
with children you do not experience directly, there's no moral weight
here.
Or is there? from Peter Unger, "Living and Letting Die." Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996.
Women Dancing, Senegal

back to top
XII. In the Case of the Drowning Child in the Pond John was the
only one
who could save the child at that moment; whereas there are many
others
much wealthier than I am who could send money to UNICEF.
To many people, a promising difference between the two contrast
cases is
this: John is the only one who can save the child from drowning, i.e.,
using a
bit of jargon to highlight tthis feature of the Shallow Pond case, John
is her
"unique potential savior." But, in the case of The Envelope, there are
more
than enough well-off people to get the distant children saved; using
kindred
jargon, in that case there are "multiple potential saviors." Because
John is the
child's unique potential savior, mightn't he have a great
responsibility
toward the the child? But because you're only one of many multiple
potential saviors, you might not have much responsibility toward the
Envelope's children. That's why, in that case, your behavior, tossing
the
envelope into the wastebasket, isn't wrong.
But, to our moral common sense, isn't this nonsense? You know full
well that, even though they
can do so, almost all the other well-off folks won't aid the needy
children. You know that, for
all they'd do, even if a good many of them contributed to UNICEF,
there'd still be children in
dire need. So, while many others who sent no money behaved badly,
you did, too. Consider the
following variant of the Shallow Pond case:
Multiple Potential Saviors in Gucci
Shoes
The path from John's dorm room to Shiffman passes a shallow
ornamental pond. On his way to the Philosophy class, John,
who is walking along with three of his friends, all from the Human
Rights class, notices that a small child has fallen in and is in danger
of drowning. His friends notice this, too. If any one of them wades
in and pulls the child out, it will mean getting their clothes muddy
and either missing the Philosophy class or delaying it until they
can find something clean and dry to wear. Imagine, too, they are
also wearing a brand new pairs of Gucci shoes which they are
"breaking in" for the first time. Assume that it is evident from the
circumstances that there is no time for anybodyto take off their
shoes if there is any hope of saving the child and that John and his
friends can "see" that this is so. If anyone tries to save the child,
their shoes will become wet and be ruined beyond repair. To
replace the shoes will cost the person $100. If all four of these
people pass by the child, then, while they'll make the Human
Rights class on time, the child will die straightaway. All four
(including John) head straight for the Philosophy class and, as
expected, the child dies.
Is John's conduct any less bad, because three of his friends behaved
badly, too.
Perhaps there is "comfort" in numbers, so it is possible to say to
oneself, "I
may not be helping children in need, but I am not the only one, not
the only
who is failing to help, there are many others who could help, far
wealthier
than I am, and they aren't helping." But is this "comfort" any moral
consolation? from Peter Unger, "Living and Letting Die." Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996.
Women Planting, Mozambique

back to top
XIII. In the Case of the Drowning Child in the Pond there was just
one
person in need of being saved; whereas there is a "vast multitude" in
need of
saving as part of UNICEF's program.
When thinking of the Envelope case, we may feel overwhelmed by
the
enormous multitude of seriously needy children: we may think to
ourselves
"In the face of that vast multitude, my efforts are virtually useless."
But
given this feeling of futility, of hopelessness, is there something to
distinguish between the Envelope case and the Drowning Child? At
first, it
may seem so: "In the Shallow Pond case, there was just a single
individual in
need; in the Envelope, there are so many altogether in a vast
multitude.
But, isn't it also true that the drowning child is also just one of the
very many
greatly needy children in the world. And, while there are certain
perspectives
from which she'll seem an especially singular figure, that's also true
of every
last one of the needy children whose will be saved through UNICEF.
So, in
point of even mathematical fact, neither thoughts of the multitude
nor
thoughts of particular individuals can mark any distinction at all
between our
two cases. Or can they? from Peter Unger, "Living and Letting Die." Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996.
Weaver, Bolivia

back to top
XIV. Aid to those children that UNICEF is trying to
help should be
the
responsibility of governments and should not be the responsibility of
privately run charities and certainly not my responsibility.
When thinking of the likes of the Envelope, many entertain the
thought of
the governments: "Toward aiding the distant needy children, a
person like
me, who's hardly a billionaire, can do hardly anything. But, through
taxation
of both people like me and also billionaires, our government can do a
great
deal. Indeed, so wealthy is our country that the government can do
just about
everything that's most needed. What's more, if our government
joined with
the governments of other wealthy nations, like France and Germany
and
Japan, then, for any one of the very many well-off people in all the
wealthy
nations, the financial burden would be very easily affordable. And,
since
making one's tax payments is a routine affair, the whole business
would be
nearly automatic. Just so, these governments really ought to stop so
many
children from dying young. And, since they really ought to do the
job, it's all
right for me not to contribute." What do you make of this fairly
common
line of thought?
Well, whatever it precisely means, you might believe that
governments
ought to contribute, annually, the tens of billions of dollars that
would ensure
that only a tiny fraction of the world's poorest children suffer
seriously. And
then, whatever it means, it's even true that, their conduct is seriously
wrong
if they fail to contribute. But, what's the relevance of that to
assessing your
own behavior, and John's? If you know full well that, for all
thatgovernments do and do not do, each year millions of Third World
children die from easily preventable causes and kmnowing that your
$100
will prevent the deaths of thirty moree children, what difference
does the
failure of governments to act on your failure to contribute?
Doesn't it appear that in morally important respects, in the Envelope
your
situation vis-a-vis that envelope from UNICEF is the same as
a group
of four
students, all in their Gucci shoes, who walk by the drwoning child in
the
Shallow Pond, no? If all three of John's friends fail to help the child
in need,
does that somehow let John off the hook? Similarly, in the Envelope
case it
is harder for you to do as much for distant needy children than it is
for the
most wealthy governments, and perhaps the cost to you is, will be, in
some
respects, proportionately greater. And so it's also credible that, in
the
Envelope case, your tossing the envelope into the wastebasket isn't
as bad as a
wealthy government's failure to act. But are you only thinking of
degrees of
badness here or is there something to the thought that governments
ought to
help and you need not feel in any way obligated to do so? from Peter Unger, "Living and Letting Die." Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996.
Maybe the point is that all of us should do more? Is that the point?
In this
respect, perhaps you think it is more important to be politically
active, more
important to lobby in the interests of children in need than to give
directly to
UNICEF. But as
Peter Singer might say, "Why not do both?" Is
believing that
aid to children in need in foreign lands is the government's
responsibility a
justification for not giving or merely an excuse not to give yourself?
As Peter Singer has pointed out, it si sometimes thought that "giving
privately allows the government to escape its responsibility?" Is
that also part
of the thought here? "That the more people there are who give
through
voluntary agencies, the less likely it is that the government will do
its part?"
In response to this, Singer has argued "that if no gives voluntarily
the
government will assume that its citizens are not in favor of overseas
aid, and
will cut its program accordingly. In any case, unless there is a
definite
probability that be refusing to give we would be helping to bring
about an
increase in government assistance, refusing to give privately is
wrong since it
would then be a refusal to prevent a definite evil for the sake of a
very
uncertain gain." What do you think?
Man with Donkey Plow, Eritrea

back to top
XV. Even if I do send the $100 to UNICEF, there'll still
be many
children
very prematurely dying. Indeed, no matter what I do, there'll still
be, for very
many years, very many children dying from easily preventable
causes.
In this thought, is there something to distinguish between our two
cases,
between John's conduct and your conduct? At first, it may seem so:
"Unlike
the Envelope's distant children, the Drowning Child presented John
with a
particular distinct problem. If only he waded in and pulled the child
out, the
problem would have been completely resolved. Starting with just
such a
problem, John would finish with nothing less than a completely
cleaned
scene. But even if I contribute to UNICEF and save
thirty more
children from
dying, there will be a continuing mess involving all those distant
children
who did not receive aid!"
Is this appearance illusory: Isn't the drowning child just as much a
part of the
"continuing mess in the world" as the distant children UNICEF is
trying to
help? As has long been true, and as will long remain true, the world
has
people who drown. If distant children are part of a "continuing
mess," so is
the drowning child, no? Neither saving the drowning child nor
sending $100
to UNICEF will offer
the chance of transforming the world into a
cleaned
scene. from Peter Unger, "Living and Letting Die." Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996.
Woman with Basket, Senegal

back to top
XVI. The child in need in the case of the Shallow Pond is an
emergency;
whereas the situation of the children in the case of The Envelope is
not.
First of all, is this really true, and second, if it is, does this provide us
with a
moral ground for distinguishing between the two cases?
Shared with many other emergencies, what are the main points to
note about
the Shallow Pond incident? Well, until recently,this particular child
was
doing reasonably all right; at least, her main needs were regularly
met. Then,
all of a sudden, things got worse for her and, for the first time in a
long time,
she had a big need on the verge of not being met. In the case of the
children
on whose behalf UNICEF is making its
appeal, however, these distant
little
children were always in at least pretty bad straits. And, in their part
of the
world, for a long time many people's great needs weren't met and,
consequently, those many suffered seriously. But, then, even as
there's no
emergency in the case of the Envelope, the situation' it seeks to
address is far
worse than almost any emergency. To highlight this, we may say
that, in the
situation that the Envelope seeks to address, there's a chronic horror.
Indeed,
during the very few years they've had before dying, those children
were
among the worst off people in the world, while the child in the
Shallow Pond
had a few years of a reasonably good life. So now it would seem that
not
helping in the envelope case, tossing the envelope into the
wastebasket,
requires an even stronger justification, no?
For a more fine-grained picture of emergencies, it's useful to look at
the
cyclone- prone country of Bangladesh, where about 15 million
people, out of
about 115 million, live in the vulnerable coastal region. The victim of
7 of the
century's 10 worst cyclones, in the past 25 years 3 big ones struck
Bangladesh.
When the 1970's big cyclone struck the unprepared country, the
windstorm
killed about 3 million, about 2.5 million succumbing, in the storm's
devastating aftermath, to waterborne disease. Far beyond just
helping to
prompt the writing of Singer's "Famine, Affluence and Morality," this
disaster "sparked the founding of Oxfam America," about 25 years
after the
original Oxfam was founded in Oxford, England. With help from such
foreign non-governmental organizations (NGO's), and with hard work
by
Bangladeshi groups and individuals, by 1991 a lot was done to make
the
country's people less vulnerable to killing winds; when a big cyclone
hit
Bangladesh that year, only(!?) about 130 thousand folks were killed,
a
dramatic improvement. But, still, a great many poor people still had
to bury
their children, or their parents, or their spouses, or their siblings, or
their best
friends. So, with continued support from far and near, Bangladeshis
continued to work hard. So, by 1994 they had built 900 cleverly
designed
cyclone shelters, each able to protect thousands of people. Here's the
first
sentence of the piece in Oxfam America News commenting on the
result:
"On May 2, a 180 mph cyclone pummeled southeastern coastal
Bangladesh,
claiming just under 200 lives." Though it looks like there's a
misprint, that's
as well ordered as it's well warranted.
For ever so many years, really, but, especially in more recent years,
most in
the world's poorest countries, including Bangladesh, have lives that
are
actively effective, socially committed, and part of a palpable upward
trend;
their lives are clearly well worth living. When thinking whether to
help
these materially poor people, so that more and more of them will
bury fewer
and fewer of their children, it's useful to have that in mind.
Regarding emergencies, what's to be found in our responses to the
cases?
Perhaps, the following may be useful:
"In the case of the Shallow Pond, the child is in immediate danger;
with
relatively little effort John can remove her from danger. Through no
fault of
our own, our lives and welfare may be jeopardized. Admittedly
some acute
need results from our ignorance or stupidity. Even so, others should
assist us
when feasible, at least if the cost to them is slight. After all, even the
most
careful person
occasionally makes mistakes. When need is caused by natural
disaster or
personal error, we each want others to come to our aid. Indeed, we
think they
should come to our aid. If, upon reflection, our desire for assistance
is
reasonable when we are in need, then, by extension, we should
acknowledge
that we should help others in similar need. Shared responsibility
and
sympathy conspire to create the sense that we should go to the aid of
those
who cannot alleviate their own acute needs.
"Our common vulnerability to circumstances and to the "scanty
provision
nature has made" leads us to seek ways to protect ourselves against
misfortune and error. Natural disasters occur. They may occur
where I live;
they may not. Prudent people will recognize that we are all more
secure, and
thus, better off, if we recognize a shared responsibility to assist
others in acute
need.
"This responsibility is all the more apparent when those in need
cannot care
for themselves and are in no way responsible for their plight. In
short, the
responsibility is greatest (and less contentious) when children are
the victims.
In fact, when children are in acute need, especially when many are
in a
position to help, there's little moral difference between the
responsibility of
biological parents and others. If a child is drowning, then even if the
parents
(or some third party) tossed the child into the pond (and are thus
singularly
responsible for the child's plight), we should still rescue her if we
can.
Likewise, if a child is starving, and her need is acute, then even if the
child's
parents and its government have acted irresponsibly, we should still
feed the
child if we can.
"Arguably the problem is different if the acute need is so substantial
and so
widespread as to require us to make considerable sacrifices to help
those in
need. In this case our responsibilities to the children in acute need
may
resemble our responsibilities to children in chronic need.
"Acute need arises once (or at least relatively infrequently). It
requires
immediate action, which, if successful, often alleviates the need. But
most
hunger is not acute, it is chronic. Chronic hunger is the hunger of
persistently malnourished children, where the causes of hunger are
neither
episodic nor easily removed. If the need can be met at all, it can be
met only
through more substantial, sustained effort, and often only by making
numerous (and perhaps fundamental) institutional changes, both
within our
countries, and the other countries in need of aid.
"That is why Singer's case is disanalogous with most world hunger.
The
drowning child is in acute need. Suppose, however, that Singer's
fictional
child lives on the edge of a pond where she is relatively
unsupervised. We
cannot protect this child by simply dirtying our clothes once. Rather,
we must
camp on the pond's edge, poised to rescue her whenever she falls or
slips into
the water. However, can we reasonably expect anyone to devote her
entire
life (or even the next six years) as this child's lifeguard? It is difficult
to see
how. The expectation seems even less appropriate if there are many
children living beside the pond.
"Likely the only sensible way to protect the child from harm is to
relocate her
away from the pond. Or perhaps we could teach her to swim. But
are we
responsible to make these efforts? Do we have the authority to
forcibly
relocate the child or to erect an impregnable fence around the pond?
Can we
require her to take swimming lessons? Can we force her government
to
make substantial internal economic and political changes? In short,
even
though we are morally responsible to assist those in acute need (and
especially children), we cannot straight-forwardly infer that we must
assist
those (even children) in chronic need.
"For instance, if we try to save a child from famine, we may have
reason to
think that quick action will yield substantial results. Not so with
chronic
hunger. Since we are less likely to see the fruits of our efforts and,
we may be
less motivated to assist. Moreover, some have argued that we can
alleviate
chronic need only if we exert enormous effort, over a long period of
time. If
so, expecting someone to respond to chronic need arguably burdens
her
unduly. Responsible people need not spend all their time and
resources
helping those in chronic need, especially if there is only a small
chance of
success.
"Consider the following analogy which illuminates that insight.
Suppose an
adult builds a house by the side of a river that floods every few
years. After
the first flood we may help them, thinking we should respond to
someone
who appears to be in acute need. However, after the second or third
flood, we
will feel it is asking too much of us to continue to help. We would
probably
conclude that this adult has intentionally chosen a risky lifestyle.
They have
made their own bed; now they must sleep in it. Although this case
may well
be disanalagous to the plight of starving adults † since most have
little
control over the weather, soil erosion, or governmental policy †
nonetheless, many people in affluent nations think it is analogous.
"What is indisputable, however, is the case is totally disanalogous to
the
plight of children. Children did not choose to live in an economically
deprived country or in a country with a corrupt government. Nor
can they
abandon their parents and relocate in a land of plenty, or in a
democratic
regime. Hence, they are completely innocent † in no sense did they
cause
their own predicament. Moreover, they are paradigms of
vulnerability.
"Since they are the principal victims of chronic malnutrition, it is
inappropriate to refuse to help them unless someone can show that
assisting
them would require an unacceptable sacrifice. That, of course,
demands that
we draw a line between reasonable and unreasonable sacrifice. We
do not
know how to draw that line. Perhaps, though, before drawing the line
we
should ask: if it were our child who was starving, where would we
want the
line to be drawn?"
(from Hugh LaFolette & Larry May, "Suffer the Children" in
World
Hunger and Morality. Ed. William Aiken and Hugh LaFolette.
Prentice Hall:
Princeton, New Jersey, 1998)
Coffee Farmer, El Salvador

back to top
XVII. When someone will drown very soon unless you help her,
it's
morally required that you aid. But, if there's lots of time before
anything
much happens, aiding isn't morally required.
Often, it's especially important to act when matters are urgent.
Urgency is not quite the same
thing as an emergnecy, but it's close. Mightn't this be a ground for
judging your conduct in the
Envelope case more leniently than John's conduct?
It's plenty obvious that, in the case of the Shallow Pond, there's
plenty of urgency: If John
doesn't get his feet wet pretty quickly, the child will die. And, it
appears that, in the case of
sending money to UNICEF, there's no
urgency: Even if you put $100
in the mailbox just a minute
from now, it will take at least a couple of weeks for that to translate
into life-saving aid for
anyone. What's more, if you don't send anything right away, you can
do it later, say, next
month. Soon or not so soon, just as many, thirty children, will be
prevented from dying.
In these thoughts of a contrast, however, is there clarity or
confusion? It is undoubtedly true
that, in many cases, it's important both to act promptly and to have
one's conduct determined by
a clear sense of who's in the most imminent danger. Is it possible
that just as the Shallow
Pond's a case with morally important urgency, so is the case of the
Envelope?
What do you think? Well, consider the following two cases. For both,
we'll make these
suppositions:
In room A, John is tied down with rope and, next to him, a time
bomb's set to go off in just an
hour. Unless he's untied and released from the room, its explosion
will kill him. The same for
room B, except the bomb in room B is set to go off in 24 hours and
Alice is in room B. She is tied
down with rope and, next to her, a time bomb's set to go off in 24
hours. Unless she's untied and
released from the room, its explosion will kill her. You can save
either John or Alice, but not
both.
For the first case, from what you know so far, it is quite natural to
assume if you save John in
room A, there will not only still be time for someone to save Alice in
B, but, during the extra 23
hours, Alice will enjoy extra chances for rescue that John never could
have had.
But now, for the second case, make the additional assumption that
there aren't any extra
chances even for Alice in B and that you know this with absolute
certainty, beyond what you'll
do soon.
In the first case, clearly you must save John in A, but, what of the
second case? Well, in some
sense, perhaps it's still true that John's in a more urgent situation
than Alice. But, still, there's
little reason to favor aiding him. So it seems, from cases such as
these, what moral weight
attaches to urgency is due to the lesser chances of avoiding serious
loss that, normally but not
inevitably, are found in situations where there's little time to save
the day. But, between the
case of the Shallow Pond and the the case of the Envelope, there's
never any such difference in
the chances. Or is there? What more can be said to enlighten
ourselves on this score?
Well, there's a continual flow of aid from some of the world's well-off
folks to many of the most
seriously needy. At it's far end, every day there are thousands of
children on the very brink of
death. Today, their vital need is a very urgent. In the case of some
40,000 of these children,
this will be proven by the fact that, even as their need won't be met
today, by tomorrow they'll
be dead. Of course, just as urgent are the needs of thousands of
others who, only through
receiving today some very timely ORT, won't be dead tomorrow or,
happily, any time soon. To
be sure, there are many more thousands of children whose vital
needs today aren't so very
urgent: For over 40,000 of these, in just two days, their needs will
be that urgent. And, for over
40,000 others, in just three days they'll have such terribly urgent
needs; and so on. Just so, for
over forty thousand still other needy youngsters, their last day alive
with danger will be in 30
days, or 31, that is, just a month from now.
Consider these "monthers." In some respect, it may be true that,
over the next month, their
needs will become more and more urgent. But, since we can be
certain that, if you don't donate to
UNICEF soon, more
of these "monthers" will die, what moral
relevance can any such increase in
urgency have for your behavior? Clearly, none at all, no?
By contrast, what matters is that, very soon, you begin to lessen the
number of children who die
a month from now and that, then, you help lessen the number who
die shortly after that, and so
on. So, facts like it's taking a month for your mailed check to have a
vital impact aren't
morally significant. To think otherwise is like thinking that, in the
second case of the two
rooms, saving John in A is morally much better than saving Alice.
But as we saw, there seemed
to be little reason, in the second case, to come to John's aid rather
than Alice's
In morally relevant respects, it's as if each greatly needy child is like
a man or a woman in a
room, tied down with a rope, with a time bomb set to explode. Some
children's bombs are set to
go off around noon tomorrow; others' are set for five days hence; still
others' are set for a month
from now. But, since it's certain that, for all everyone else will do,
even in a month's time many
of the children still won't have their ropes untied, and so in these
different settings there's
precious little moral weight to saving some children right away or
saving some children a
little later. Because the ways of the world are slow to improve for
quite awhile, remarks like
these will be quite true, will they not? And, that's more certain than
that you yourself will be
alive a day from now. So, our moral common sense seems to deliver
the message: As for morally
weighty urgency, there's plenty in the case of the Shallow Pond and
there's plenty in the case
of The Envelope. Or is this wrong? Is this not the way to think about
urgency?
Say you still think urgency is key, that it helps to explain the
difference in your moral
judgment of John who fails to save the child from drowning and your
moral judgment of yourself,
if you were to toss the Envelope from UNICEF and its
contents into
the wastebasket. would your
judgment of your conduct in the Envelope Case change if we added a
bit of urgency to it?
Consider the following:
Super-Express Fund
The most bizarre thing in your mail today is an appeal from the SEF
or Super
Express Fund: By calling a certain number and using any major credit
card, you
can donate $500 to the SEF right away, night or day. The effect of
such a
prompt donation will be that one more child will receive ORT this
very day
and, in consequence, won't soon die. Of course, the SEF's appeal
makes clear
the reason that it will cost so much to provide ORT to just one child:
Upon
hearing from you, your credit card donation is attended to
personally,
directly, and completely. So, moments after your call, a certain ORT
packet is
rushed to the nearest international airport, whisked to the next jet
bound for
Africa, and so on. Eventually, in a remote region, a paramedic rushes
from a
speeding vehicle. After examining several dying children, he chooses
one
that, certainly, is today on the very brink of death. Then, he rapidly
mixes
the solution and administers it to just that most urgently needy little
child.
But, you don't ever make such a call and, in consequence, one more
child dies
than if you'd made the requested donation.
Do you think any worse of yourself for failing to contribute to the
Super Express Fund than you
thought of yourself for failing to contribute to the appeal from
UNICEF in the case
of The
Envelope? Does urgency make a difference? from Peter Unger, "Living and Letting Die." Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996.
Woman in Field, Ethiopia

back to top
XVIII. If John saved the child from drowning, his aid would have
been causally focused on
that particular needy child; whereas in the case of The Envelope ,
even if I'd behaved
helpfully and mailed in my check, there'd never be anyone for whom
I'd have made the
difference between suffering a serious loss and suffering none.
A distinction between causally focused aid and causally amorphous
aid is similar to several
other differences that might be proposed to mark a moral difference
between the case of the
Shallow Pond and the case of The Envelope, but is nonethless worthy
of consideration in its own
right. If John had provided aid to the drowning child, his helpful
behavior would've been
causally focused on that particular needy person. Next, causally
amorphous aid: In the case of
the Envelope, even if you'd behaved helpfully, there'd never be a
child of whom it would be
true that, had you sent in $100, she wouldn't have died prematurely.
Rather, on one end of a
causal chain, there are many donors contributing together and, on
the other, there are all the
people saved by the large effort they together support. The more
support given, the more
children saved. Does this provide a moral ground for being more
lenient, less hard on someone,
who tosses the appeal from UNICEF into the
wastebasket?
But surely, since there's nothing morally objectionable about
proceeding to aid greatly needy
folks amorphously, no moral weight attaches to the precise character
of the causal relations
between the well-off and those whom, whether collectively or not,
they might help save. The
morally important thing is that the vulnerable don't suffer, no?
would you be more inclined to
respond to UNICEF's appeal if it
were causally focused, and, if so,
would your becoming so
inclined suddenly carry moral weight?
The Special Relations Fund
You receive material from a group that assures you they'll find a
very,
very ill, little child that your money, if you contribute, will prevent
from
dying prematurely. Since very many, very, very ill, little children are
out there, this won't be terribly difficult, or costly, but neither will it
be
very cheap and easy to have your vital aid be causally focused: So, if
you
donate $100 to the SRF, while only one less child will die soon, the
group
will ensure that your donations makes the big difference for the one
child. But, you send nothing and, in consequence, one more child dies
than
would have lived had you made the requested donation. from Peter Unger, "Living and Letting Die." Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996.
Mother and Child, Senegal

back to top
XIX. If John saves the child from drowning, he provides a
service for a needy person;
whereas in the case of The Envelope , if I behave helpfully, all I have
to provide is
money.
In the case of the Shallow Pond, to provide apt aid John must
perform a service forthe child in
need. Moreover, one of his goods would be needed in the
performance of the service, namely, his
Gucci shoes. By contrast, in the case of The Envelope all you must
contribute is money; and,
beyond the trivial effort needed to mail the money, the monetary
cost is all you incur. Can this
difference favor a lenient judgment of your tossing UNICEF's appeal
into your wastebasket?
Often, the difference between mere money and, on the other side,
actual goods and services, has
a psychological impact on us: When there's a call for our money,
generally we think of what's
going on as just charity. And, when thinking this, it seems all right to
decline. But, at least in
blatantly urgent situations, when there's a call for services, or one of
our especially apt goods, a
fair number of us think we must rise to the occasion. Does this
difference have much moral
relevance?
What does your moral common sense tell you on this score: Does it
matter whether it's money,
or goods, or services, or whatever, that's needed from you to lessen
serious suffering. There isn't
a stronger moral call on you when it's your goods or services that are
needed aid than when it's
just your money or is there?
When disasters strike, like earthquakes, hurricanes, or floods,
organizations work to aid the
imperilled victims. On many of us, these groups often call only for
our money. But, on some,
they call for goods or services: For example, one good group may
suggest that, since you're well
placed in the pharmaceutical industry, you might make calls to your
associates, asking them to
donate medicines needed by victims of last week's disaster. But,
plenty often, in these ordinary
cases, the needs aren't salient to the agent approached and, then, our
uncritical reactions are
lenient. So, plenty often, the fact that what's needed is an agent's
services, or his or her goods,
doesn't affect our responses to cases. But perhaps you think it does
or you think it should affect
our responses to the two cases at hand? How can this be made out?
from Peter Unger, "Living and Letting Die." Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996.
Fishermen, Peru

back to top
XX. If John saved the child from drowning, he'd know, when all
was done, whom he
saved; whereas in the case of The Envelope I don't know whom I am
saving from an early
death.
So, even if you donated the $100 requested in the case of The
Envelope, and even if you thereby
helped save some people, you wouldn't know which children you
helped save from an early
death, or even aided at all. In the case of the Shallow Pond, by
contrast, John would know
whom he aided. Can this favor a more lenient judgment of your
conduct in the case of The
Envelope? What does your common sense tell you? Does it matter
morally whether you come to
know whose dire needs you help meet? Consider the following:
The Very Special Relations Fund
Not only does the VSRF (Very Special Relations Fund) make sure
your $200 will go to save the
life of a certain particular child, but it makes sure you'll get to know
which child that is. By
providing you with her name and a picture of the child saved, you'll
know precisely which
child's life just your donation served to spare. Still, you don't send
anything and, in consequence,
one more child soon dies than if you'd made the requested
donation.
Does your judgment of your own conduct in this more epistemically
focused case change from your
judgment of your conduct in the original case, where you do not
know whom your $100 will save?
Now consider the following:
The Vintage Boat
John's one real luxury in his life is a vintage power boat. In
particular, he is very happy with
the fine wood trim of the handsome old boat. Now, there's been a big
shipwreck in the waters
off the coast where his boat's docked. From the pier, in plain view
several hundred are
struggling. Though both Coast Guard boats and private boats are
already on their way to the
people, more boats are needed. Indeed, the more private boats out
and back soon, the more
people will be saved. But, it's also plain that, if John goes out, still,
owing to all the melee,
nobody will ever know which people will have been benefited by
John. Indeed, for each of the
people in distress whom John might bring in, it will be true to say
this: For all anyone will ever
know, that person might have been brought in by another boat, in
which case some other person,
whom some other boat rescued, would've perished. On the other
hand, this John does know:
While there's no risk at all to him, if he goes out, his boat's wood trim
will get badly damaged,
and he'll have to pay for expensive repairs. So, he leaves his boat in
dock and, as a
consequence, a few more plainly struggling people in distress soon
drown. from Peter Unger, "Living and Letting Die." Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996.
So what are your intuitions here? Do you like John any better now?
Women in Rice Paddy, Vietnam

back to top
XXI. John should save the child from drowning, but it's not wrong
for me not to contribute to
UNICEF because we should look after those near to us, our families,
and then to the children
who are in need in our own country, before we think about poor and
dying children in other far-off places.
Here's what Peter Singer has to say about this particular concern:
"No doubt we do
instinctively prefer to help those who are close to us. Few could
stand by and watch a child
drown; many can ignore a famine in Africa. But the question is not
what we usually do, but
what we ought to do, and it is difficult to see any sound moral
justification for the view that
distance, or community membership, makes a crucial difference to
our obligations.
"Consider, for instance, racial affinities. Should people of European
origin help poor Europeans
before helping poor Africans? . . . People's need for food has nothing
to do with their race. . .
The same point applies to citizenship or nationhood. Every affluent
nation has some
relatively poor citizens, but absolute poverty is limited largely to the
poor nations. Those
living on the streets of Calcutta, or in the drought-prone Sahel region
in Africa, are
experiencing poverty unknown to the West. Under these
circumstances it would be wrong to
decide that only those fortunate enough to be citizens of our own
community will share our
abundance.
"We feel obligations of kinship more strongly than those of
citizenship. Which parents could
give away their last bowl of rice if their own children were starving?
To do so would seem
unnatural, contrary to our nature as biologically evolved beings,
although whether it would be
wrong is another question altogether. In any case, we are not faced
with that situation, but
with one in which our own children are well-fed, well-educated, and
would now like new bikes,
a stereo set, or their own car. In these circumstances, any special
obligations we might have to
our children have been fulfilled and the needs of strangers make a
stronger claim upon us.
"The element of truth in the view that we should first take care of
our own. lies in the
advantage of a recognized system of responsibilities. when families
and local communities look
after their own poorest members, ties of affection and personal
relationships achieve ends that
would otherwise require a large, impersonal bureaucracy. Hence it
would be absurd to propose
that from now on we regard ourselves as equally responsibile for the
welfare of everyone in the
world; but an obligation to assist does not propose that. It applies
only when some are in
absolute poverty, and others can help without sacrificing anything of
comparable moral
significance; and before that point had been reached, the breakdown
of the system of family
and community responsibility would be a factor to weigh the balance
in favor of a small degree
of preference for family and community. This small degree of
preference is, however,
decisively outweighed by existing discrepancies."
Young Girl, Vietnam

back to top
XXII. If I donate to UNICEF, I'll just help
create a situation, in the
further future, when
there'll be disastrously more children painfully dying. So, it's
actually better to throw away
the envelope. At the very least, it's not wrong.
When thinking about cases like the Envelope, many often have some
thought of the disastrous
further future: "If I help prevent some of these young children from
dying soon, then, years from
now, they'll produce yet more children, worsening the population
explosion that, more than
anywhere else, goes on precisely where there are so many imperilled
children.
But is this just another excuse not to give or is there substance to this
concern? Doesn't it require
us to know much, much more about population explosion,
overpopulation, population control,
and so on, to begin to even think about this concern fully? And if it
were true, that saving thirty
children from dying now will only make for more pressure on the
population of the planet,
albeit quite miniscule, is this a way of distinguishing between the
two cases, between John's
saving the child from drowning and my sending money to UNICEF?
Say John notices (he has a very keen eye) that the child who has
fallen into the shallow pond
is from Bangladesh. Say he knows this because a couple and their
five children from the porest
regions of Bangladesh are visiting Brandeis to talk with students
about the food crisis there.
They plan to return shortly top their country and the region from
which they have come.
UNICEF has made
arrangements for them to visit so that students
might have the opportunity
to speak directly to a family that is experiencing the hardships
talked about in the question for the Final in the Philosophy class as part of a newly sponsored
UNICEF Program:
"Operation Wake-Up." Imagine, too, that John is one of those persons
in the Philosophy class who has expressed concern about the long-term consequences
of saving children through
UNICEF's ORT
Project on the future population of countries like
Bangladesh.
So there's John at
the edge of the pond in his brand new Gucci shoes and he's overcome
his worry about the
damage his shoes will suffer if he comes to this child's aid. But now
just as he's about to wade
into the pond and pull the child to safety, the following thoughts
flood his mind: "If I save
this child from drowning, her parents will take her back to
Bangladesh and she'll probably
grow up to be a very attractive person and give birth to many little
Bangladeshi's. But if I do
not save her from drowning and head straight for the Human Rights
class to the hospital, then,
she won't be able to contribute to any further population explosion
further down the road and to
a disastrous dying of Bangladeshi's many years hence. So a quick
calculation of the future
effects upon world population of my being a Good Samaritan in this
particular instance, it's best
for all concerned that get myself to the Philosophy class and leave
this child to drown. In
any event, if someone were to ask me what I did, I shall at least be
able to say I did what was
best in the long run, and if anyone has any difficulty accepting that
analysis, I won't have
behaved badly."
If John were to act in this way with the accompanying rationale
above for his having acted as
he did, would you think anymore leniently of his behavior than your
judgment of his behavior
in the "original" case of the Shallow Pond?
Does this variant of the Shallow Pond case suggest that the effects of
sending money to
UNICEF on the
world population or future generations are not
morally relevant? What do yout
think? Garret Hardin
makes a case for
population control through famine and starvation, what is the
evidence on the other side?
Some believe and argue that, contrary to Hardin, the available
evidence strongly supports the
thought that decreasing childhood mortality stabilizes population. To
be sure, the
increasingly widespread availability of modern contraceptives is
partly responsible for the
recent big decreases in how fast the world's population is growing, as
many studies show. If you
are concerned about population control, this is one reason, even if
perhaps not the most
important reason, to support the International Planned Parenthood
Federation, or IPPF. With
maternal mortality still standing at about 500,000 women a year,
IPPF is also cutting down the
number and, so, lessening the number of children, still in the
millions, who each year become
motherless, although if you are concerned with over-population this
may make support of the
IPPF more complicated for you. Also in IPPF clinics, many in the
developing countries receive
the basic health care they need. Perhaps the greatest of all IPPF
affiliates, Colombia's
PROFAMILIA supports some clinics for men only. Owing to that, the
terribly macho attitudes
of many Colombian men have become much less macho, a big benefit
to many Colombian women.
At all events, in Colombia there's occurring a population success
story. The IPPF's most relevant
address is:
International
Planned Parenthood Federation
International Planned Parenthood Federation
Western Hemisphere Region, Inc.
902 Broadway - 10th Floor
New York, NY 10010
IPPF Affiliate Organizations and Programs:
UNAIDS: The Joint United Nations
Programme on HIV/AIDS
United Nations
United Nations Children's Fund
(UNICEF)
United Nations Development
Programme
United Nations Office in Geneva
United Nations Population Fund
United Nations Population Information
Network (POPIN)
United Nations Economic Comission for Europe (UNECE)
World Bank
World Health Organization
Worldwatch
Canadian International Development
Agency (CIDA)
United Kingdom Department for
International Development (DfID)
United States Agency for
International Development (USAID)
WOMANKIND
Worldwide
Abortion Access
Project
Action Canada for Population
Development
Association of Reproductive Health
Professionals (ARHP)
Alan Guttmacher Institute
Baylor College of Medicine
Catholics for a Free
Choice (CFFC)
The Centre for Development and Population
Activities (CEDPA)
The Center for Reproductive Law and
Policy
The Consortium for Emergency
Contraception (CEC)
Demographic and Health
Surveys
Deutsche Gesellschaft für Technische
Zusammenarbeit (GTZ)
Developments: the International
Development Magazine (produced by DFID)
Doctors of the
World
Earth Times newspaper
Endometriosis Association
EngenderHealth
Face to Face Campaign
Family Care
International
Family Health International
Family Planning Council of Pennsylvannia
FORWARD Foundation for
Women's Health, Research and Development (Campaign against FGM)
German Foundation for World Population
(Deutsche Stiftung Weltbevoelkerung)
Global
Reproductive Health Forum at Harvard
Inter-European Parliamentary
Forum on Population and Development
JAMWA, Journal of the American Medical Women's Association
The International
Community of Women Living with HIV/AIDS
International Family
Health
International Women's Health Coalition
(IWHC)
IPAS
JHPIEGO Corporation
Johns Hopkins University Center for
Communication Programs
Johns Hopkins University Population
Center
JOICFP (Japanese Organization for
International Cooperation in Family Planning)
KNOW
HIV/AIDS- a global media campaign partnership of Viacom Inc and
the Kaiser Family Foundation
Management Sciences for Health
Margaret Sanger Papers
Project
Marie Stopes International
Para55.org (Commonwealth focus group
on HIV/AIDS)
Pathfinder International
People
& the Planet
Population Action
International
Population Communications
International
Population
Concern
Population Council
Population Institut
Population
Media Center
Population Reference Bureau
Path (Program for Appropriate Technology
in Health)
Program for the
Study of Sexuality, Gender, Health and Human Rights at Columbia University,
New York City
The Religious Consultation
on Population, Reproductive Health and Ethics
Reproductive Health Alliance
Reproductive Health Outlook (produced
by PATH)
ReproLine: Reproductive Health
Online (maintained by JHPIEGO Corp.)
Resource Center for Adolescent
Pregnancy Prevention (ReCAPP)
"See Change" Campaign - (CFFC)
Sexually Transmitted Infections
Journal
Safe Motherhood
UNESCO Youth Coordination Unit
Vasectomy Medical
World Population Foundation
(WPF)
Youth Education Learning &
Development (YIELD IRELAND)
Still, for population to stabilize, much more is needed than what the
IPPF is able to provide.
What's also needed can be seen from many perspectives. Take the
Indian state of Kerala,
highlighted in the film "The Politics of Food," for an example: Since
the Total Fertility
Rate's already down to 1.9, or even lower, population won't just
stabilize there; it will decline.
Beyond widespread availability of contraceptive means, there are
other reasons that fully
80% of Keralan couples actually use family planning measures:
Because they know the
childhood mortality rate there is very low, Keralans can be confident
that, without having
many kids, they'll have some surviving children. And, since they
know the community will
make sure their basic needs are met, Keralans know that, even
without children to rely on,
their life expectancy is high. And, since the female literacy rate is
very high, marking much
respect for women's interests, it's no surprise that in Kerala there's a
population success story.
from Peter Unger, "Living and Letting Die." Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996.
Here is Peter Singer's on "Population and the Ethics of Triage":
"Perhaps the most serious objection to the argument that we have an
obligation to assist is that since the major cause of absolute poverty
is
overpopulation, helping those now in poverty will only ensure that
yet more
people are bom to live in poverty in the future. In its most extreme
form, this
objection is taken to show that we should adopt a policy of 'triage'.
The term
comes from medical policies adopted in wartime. With too few
doctors to
cope with all the casualties, the wounded were divided into three
categories:
those who would probably survive without medical assistance, those
who
might survive if they received assistance, but otherwise probably
would not,
and those who even with medical assistance probably would not
survive.
Only those in the middle category were given medical assistance. The
idea, of
course, was to use limited medical resources as effectively as
possible. For
those in the first category, medical treatment was not strictly
necessary; for
those in the third category, it was likely to be useless.
"It has been suggested that we should apply the same policies to
countries,
according to their prospects of becoming self-sustaining. We would
not aid
countries that even without our help will soon be able to feed their
populations. We would not aid countries that, even with our help,
will not
be able to limit their population to a level they can feed. We would
aid those
countries where our help might make the difference between success
and
failure in bringing food and population into balance. Advocates of
this theory
are understandably reluctant to give a complete list of the countries
they
would place into the 'hopeless' category; Bangladesh has been cited
as an
example, and so have some of the countries of the Sahel region of
Africa.
"Adopting the policy of triage would, then, mean cutting off
assistance to
these countries and allowing famine, disease, and natural disasters to
reduce
the population of those countries to the level at which they can
provide
adequately for all. In support of this view Garrett Hardin has offered
a
metaphor: we in the rich nations are like the occupants of a crowded
lifeboat
adrift in a sea full of drowning people. If we try to save the
drowning by
bringing them aboard, our boat will be overloaded and we shall all
drown.
Since it is better that some survive than none, we should leave the
others to
drown. in the world today, according to Hardin, 'lifeboat ethics' apply.
The
rich should leave the poor to starve, for otherwise the poor will drag
the rich
down with them.
"Against this view, some writers have argued that overpopulation is
a myth.
The world produces ample food to feed its population, and could,
according to
some estimates, feed ten times as many. People are hungry not
because there
are too many but because of inequitable land distribution, the
manipulation
of third world economies by the developed nations, wastage of food
in the
West, and so on.
"Putting aside the controversial issue of the extent to which food
production
might one day be increased, it is true, as we have already seen, that
the world
now produces enough to feed its inhabitants-the amount lost by
being fed to
animals itself being enough to meet existing grain shortages.
Nevertheless
population growth cannot be ignored. Bangladesh could, with land
reform
and using better techniques, feed its present population of 115
million; but by
the year 2000, according to the United Nations Population Division
estimates,
its population will be 150 million. The enormous effort that will have
to go
into feeding an extra 35 million people, all added to the population
within a
decade, means that Bangladesh must develop at full speed to stay
where it is.
Other low-income countries are in similar situations. By the end of
the
century, Ethiopia's population is expected to rise from 49 to 66
million;
Somalia's from 7 to 9 million, India's from 853 to 1041 million,
Zaire's from
35 to 49 million. What will happen if the world population continues
to
grow? It cannot do so indefinitely.
"It will be checked by a decline in birth rates or a rise in death rates.
Those
who advocate triage are proposing that we allow the population
growth of
some countries to be checked by a rise in death rates that is, by
increased
malnutrition, and related diseases;,by widespread famines; by
increased infant
mortality; and by epidemics of infectious diseases. The consequences
of triage
on this scale are so horrible that we are inclined to reject it without
further
argument. How could we sit by our television sets, watching million
starve
while we do nothing? Would not that be the end of all notions of
human
equality and respect for human life? ... Don't people have a right to
our
assistance, irrespective of the consequences?
"Anyone whose ,~initial reaction to triage was not one of repugnance
would
be an unpleasant sort of person. Yet initial reactions based on strong
feelings
are not always reliable guides. Advocates of triage are rightly
concerned with
the long-term consequences of our actions. They say that helping the
poor
and starving now merely ensures more poor and starving in the
future.
When our capacity to help is finally unable to cope - as one day it
must be -
the suffering will be greater than it would be if we stopped helping
now.
"If this is correct, there is nothing we can do to prevent absolute
starvation
and poverty, in the long run, and so we have no obligation to assist.
Nor does
it seem reasonable to hold that under these circumstances people
have a right
to our assistance. If we do accept such a right, irrespective of the
consequences,
we are saying that, in Hardin's metaphor, we should continue to haul
the
drowning into our lifeboat until the boat sinks and we all drown. If
triage is to
be rejected it must be tackled on its own ground, within the
framework ,of
consequentialist ethics. Here it is vulnerable. Any consequentialist
ethics
must take probability of outcome into account. A course of action
that will
certainly produce some benefit is to be preferred to an alternative
course that
may lead to a slightly larger benefit, but is equally likely to result in
no benefit
at all. Only if the greater magnitude of the uncertain benefit
outweighs its
uncertainty should we choose it. Better one certain unit of benefit
than a 10
per cent chance of five units; but better a 50 per cent chance of three
units
than a single certain unit. The same principle applies when we are
trying to
avoid evils.
"The policy of triage involves a certain, very great evil: population
control by
famine and disease. Tens of millions would die slowly. Hundreds of
millions
would continue to live in absolute poverty, at the very margin of
existence.
Against this prospect, advocates of the policy place a possible evil
that is
greater still: the same process of famine and disease, taking place in,
say, fifty
years' time, when the world's population may be three times its
present level,
and the number who will die from famine, or struggle on in absolute
poverty, will be that much greater. The question is: how probable is
this
forecast that continued assistance now will lead to greater disasters
in the
future? Forecasts of population growth are notoriously fallible, and
theories
about the factors that affect it remain speculative.
"One theory, at least as plausible as any other, is that countries pass
through a
'demographic transition' as their standard of living rises. When
people are
very poor and have no access to modern medicine their fertility is
high, but
population is kept in check by high death rates. The introduction of
sanitation, modern medical techniques, and other improvements
reduces the
death rate, but initially has little effect on the birth rate. Then
population
grows rapidly. Some poor countries, especially in sub-Saharan Africa,
are now
in this phase. If standards of living continue to rise, however, couples
begin
to realise that to have the same number of children surviving to
maturity as
in the past, they do not need to give birth to as many children as
their parents
did. The need for children to provide economic support in old age
diminishes. Improved education and the emancipation and
employment of
women also reduce the birth-rate, and so population growth begins
to level
off. Most rich nations have reached this stage, and their populations
are
growing only very slowly, if at all.
"If this theory is right, there is an alternative to the disasters
accepted as
inevitable by supporters of triage. We can assist poor countries to
raise the
living standards of the poorest members of their population. We can
encourage governments of these countries to enact land reform
measures,
improve education, and liberate women from a purely child-bearing
role. We
can also help other countries to make contraception and sterilisation
widely
available. There is a fair chance that these measures will hasten the
onset of
the demographic transition and bring population growth down to a
manageable level.
"According to United Nations estimates, in 1965 the average woman
in the
third world gave birth to six children, and only 8 per cent were using
some
form of contraception; by 1991 the average number of children had
dropped to
just below four, and more than half the women in the third world
were
taking contraceptive measures. Notable successes in encouraging the
use of
contraception had occurred in Thailand, Indonesia, Mexico, Colombia,
Brazil,
and Bangladesh. This achievement reflected a relatively low
expenditure in
developing countries - considering the size and significance of the
problem -
of $3 billion annually, with only 20 per cent of this sum coming from
developed nations. So expenditure in this area seems likely to be
highly cost-
effective. Success cannot be guaranteed; but the evidence suggests
that we can
reduce population growth by improving economic security and
education,
and making contraceptives amorc widely. available.
"This prospect makes triage ethically unacceptable. We cannot allow
millions
to die from starvation and disease when there is a reasonable
probability that
population can be brought under control without such horrors.
Population
growth is therefore not a reason against giving overseas aid, although
it
should make us think about the kind of aid to give. Instead of food
handouts,
it may be better to give aid that leads to a slowing of population
growth. This
may mean agricultural assistance for the rural poor, or assistance
with
education, or the provision of contraceptive services. Whatever kind
of aid
proves most effective in specific circumstances, the obligation to
assist is not
reduced.
"One awkward question remains. What should we do about a poor
and
already overpopulated country that, for religious or nationalistic
reasons,
restricts the use of contraceptives and refuses to slow its population
growth?
Should we nevertheless offer development assistance? Or should we
make
our offer conditional on effective steps being taken to reduce the
birth-rate?
To the latter course, some would object that putting conditions on aid
is an
attempt to impose our own ideas on independent sovereign nations.
So it is-
but is this imposition unjustifiable?
"If the argument for an obligation to assist is sound, we have an
obligation to
reduce absolute poverty; but we have no obligation to make
sacrifices that, to
the best of our knowledge, have no prospect of reducing poverty in
the long
run. Hence we have no obligation to assist countries whose
governments
have policies that will make our aid ineffective. This could be very
harsh on
poor citizens of these countries-for they may have no say in the
government's policies-but we will help more people in the long run
by using
our resources where they are most effective. The same principles
may apply,
incidentally, to countries that refuse to take other steps that could
make
assistance effective-like refusing to reform systems of land holding
that
impose intolerable burdens on poor tenant farmers." - Peter Singer,
Practical Ethics.
Some useful links:
Zero
Population Growth. In their own words, " Zero
Population Growth, Inc. (ZPG) is a
national non-profit organization working to slow population growth
and achieve a
sustainable balance of people, resources, and the environment."
Bill McKibben, "A Special Moment in History,"
The Atlantic Monthly, May
1998.
Mark Sagoff, "How Many Is Too Many?,"
The Atlantic Monthly, February
1993.
Do We Consume Too Much?,"
Atlantic Monthly, June 1997.
Reviews of Do We Consume Too Much? by
Mark Sagoff and Discussions of the future of the planet
are dominated by those who believe that an expanding world
economy will use up natural
resources and those who see no reasons, environmental or
otherwise, to limit economic growth. Neither side has it
right
The Non-Trivial POP-
ulation Quiz How much do you know about the population of this
planet? Here is an opportunity for you to test your "POP
I.Q."
The world population reached six billion at the
beginning of the 1999 academic year.

In October 1999, the United Nations announced this global
demographic event. It marked the first time in human history
that any generation has witnessed the tripling of world
population, which was a mere two billion in 1930 (up from 1
billion in the early 1800's).
back to top
XXIII. John should save the child from drowning, and once he's
done so, he's "off the moral
hook," so to speak, but if I donate to UNICEF, there's hardly
any
stopping; having saved
thirty children, there'll be another thirty to save, and so on and so on
and so on.
In the case of the Shallow Pond, it's quite clear that it's a fairly rare
circumstance, not your
"every day occurrence," you might say, so once John has saved the
child, he'll be off the moral
hook for a good long while. But the case of The Envelope might
produce a radically different
response: "UNICEF's appeal is
asking me to help in a siuation that is,
alas, all too common, so
even if I behaved well in the case of The Envelope and sent $100 to
UNICEF, I'd
probably face
this situation all over again in the not so distant future. Indeed, just
you wait, shortly after I
contribute to UNICEF another letter
will arrive in my mailbox from
OXFAM and then
from CARE
and I'll have to go through the same sort of agony about
whether or not to respond to
UNICEF and if I
send money to OXFAM and CARE
, just you wait, a
new letter will arrive in my
mailbox from UNICEF, thanking me
for my contribution and asking
me for another! I'll never be
off the moral hook, never, never, never! So, between the two cases,
between the case of the
Shallow Pond and the case of The Envelope there's a huge moral
difference." Is this a sound reflection? What do you think?
So the question is: Is there a sort of distinction (say, "rare
occurrence" vs. "not-so-rare
occurrence") that can ground a strict moral judgment of John's
conduct in the case of the Shallow
Pond, but not for the case of The Envelope? At first glance, this
question seems to introduce a
new issue, a distinction different from and totally unlike any of the
distinctions we have
encountered so far. But is it a new issue?
Suppose that, though far from rich, you've already donated fully a
fourth of your income this
year to support effective programs conducted by OXFAM, UNICEF,
and CARE
. Assume you did
this by responding quite positively to the many appeals that, during
the past year, you
received from the organizations. (Of course, unless you're "one in a
million," this assumption is
likely to be false. While quite a few of us give a lot to elite
institutions, and while many give
much to local religious groups, hardly anyone gives even a fortieth of
his or her annual income
toward these programs. Each year well-off Americans give far more
to Harvard University
than to all three (OXFAM, UNICEF and CARE
) combined, and far more
to Yale (although not
to Brandeis) than all three combined; and they also give more even
to a less elite institutions,
like NYU, than to all combined. In any event, let's make the
assumption that you have
already donated a full fourth of your income to OXFAM, UNICEF and
CARE
) Assume that
before the year's over, there appears in your mailbox, complete with
material about ORT and a
return envelope, yet another appeal from UNICEF. Throwing up
your
hands, you think this:
"Even forgetting about the thousands I've given to OXFAM and CARE
this year, I've already
sent UNICEF itself
thousands of dollars. Now, I don't want to be a
Scrooge, you understand; but,
holy moly, enough is enough!" With that exasperating thought in
mind, you throw away the
most recent materia from UNICEF into your
wastebasket..
Of course, there's another half to this little story: As you are throwing
away this latest appeal
from UNICEF, John
is returing from his Philosophy class. He's
feeling quite good about
himself because contrary to expectations, he decided in the last
minute to save the child from
drowning and he told EVERYONE in the Philosophy class and the
entire class gave John a
standing ovation. So you can imagine he's feeling pretty smug as he
walks barefoot back to his
dorm room. He walks by the Shallow Pond on his way back to his
dorm and he sees another
child, a completely different, not the same child he just saved on his
way to class, but a totally
new child, same age as the last child, and apparently also about to
drown but clearly another
little girl. After watching this child for a split second or two, Joh
throws up his hands and
says, glancing heavenwards, but as much to himself as to anyone
else: "Now, I don't want to be
a Scrooge, you understand; but, holy moly, enough is enough!," And
he hurries off to his dorm
room to change his clothes and make a cup of instant hot chocolate
and, not unsurprisingly, the
child dies.
So, looking at your conduct and John's conduct in these two revisions
of the Shallow Pond and
The Envelope cases, what are your intuitive moral assessments? Is
your judgment of your own
conduct in the revised version of The envelope case just as lenient
and your judgment of John just
as harsh? And if so, what does this mean about the moral value of
the distinction now under
consideration? from Peter Unger, "Living and Letting Die." Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996.
Village Women, Ecuador

back to top
XXIV. John should save the child from drowning and to expect
no less from John is to place
no more than a reasonable demand on his conduct, but, as my
previous concern makes plain, if I
am to be judged negatively for tossing UNICEF's original
appeal into
my wastebasket that only
goes to show that there is something very wrong with morality: that
it is too highly
demanding and what needs to change, then, is not my conduct, but
our view of morality.
Peter Singer's position seems to commit us to the view that tobehave
in a way that's not
seriously wrong, even moderately well-off persons, like you and me,
are going to have to
contribute to vitally effective groups, like OXFAM and
UNICEF, most
of the money we now
have, and most of what comes our way for the foreseeable future.
And this is too demanding,
too highly demanding. And insofar as what's demanded of John for
John to be a good person in
the case of the Shallow Pond is not highly demanding, but what's
being demanded of me in the
case of The Envelope is very highly demanding indeed, the level of
the moral demands placed
on John and on me mark a difference that makes a significant moral
difference between the two
cases, no? Well, take the two following propositions:
(1) The View that Ethics is Highly Demanding is the correct view of
our moral situation.
And this other conditional proposition:
(2) (Even) if this View isn't correct, a strict judgment of my failure
to respond in the case of The
Envelope (still) won't do any more toward committing us to the View
than will a strict judgment
of John's behavior in the case of the Shallow Pond.
Now it is very liklely the case that ethics is highly demanding, highly
demanding of all of us;
that's the nature of the beast called "ethics." But, put this matter
aside for the moment, and
focus on the conditional proposition. The Conditional Proposition
suggests, (2) suggests if a
strict judgment of John's conduct in the case of the Shallow Pond
doesn't commit us to anything
very costly from a moral point of view, then neither does a strict
judgment of the conduct of a
person who tosses UNICEF's appeal into
the wastebasket commit us
to anything very costly. Is
this so?
Consider the following relatively general principle:
Lessening (the Number of People Suffering) Serious Loss. Other
things being even nearly equal,
if your behaving in a certain way will result in the number of people
who suffer serious loss
being less than the number who'll suffer that seriously if you don't
so behave (and if you won't
thereby treat another being at all badly or ever cause another any
loss at all), then it's
seriously wrong for you not to so behave.
First, what is meant by "serious loss" here? well, even if it happens
painlessly, when someone
loses her life very prematurely, she suffers a serious loss. Next,
some losses are less than
serious: There's your losing just a tooth. And, there are financial
losses from which you can
recover. Anyway, there are all sorts of losses from which you might
suffer: the loss of $100, the
loss of the means to purchase a new bicycle, the loss of a life, the loss
of a brand new pair of
Gucci shoes, and so on. Now many may resist the idea that to bring
in a concern for costs and
losses on the one hand and benefits and gains on the other is not an
appropriate set of
considerations to include in any genuine moral principle. Some folks
think see that such cares
for costs conflict with any truly decent moral thinking. And they
may, after all, be right, but
put this caveat aside for the moment.
How might it be ensured that, even when followed fully, a precept
won't ever mean a terribly
burdensome cost? Of course, the best and perhaps the only honest
way to do this is to see to it
that, in the principle itself, there's a logical guarantee to this effect.
So, consider the
following maxim:
Pretty Cheaply Lessening Early Death
Other things being even nearly equal, if your behaving in a certain
way will result in the
number of people who very prematurely lose their lives being less
than the number who'll do so
if you don't so behave and if even so you'll still be at least
reasonably well off, then it's
seriously wrong for you not to so behave.
Before moving to an even less demanding specific maxim, notice two
points about this one: First,
complying with it can't have you be less than reasonably well off!
And, second, your conduct in
the case of The Envelope's conduct gets a severe judgment from the
precept, as well as John's
conduct in the case of the Shallow Pond.
Few truly rich folks, if any at all, will fully comply with Pretty
Cheaply Lessening Early
Death. So, for any particular billionaire, the cost of compliance will
be very great: If the toll's
not taken all at once, then a decently progressive sequence will soon
turn any into someone who's
just reasonably well off. So, for a maxim that's appealing even to the
very rich, there must be a
precept that's a lot like:
Very Cheaply Lessening Early Death
Other things being even nearly equal, if your behaving in a certain
way will result in the
number of people who very prematurely lose their lives being less
than the number who'll do so
if you don't so behave and if even so, you'll still be both (a) at least
reasonably well off and (b)
very nearly as well off as you ever were, then it's seriously wrong
for you not to so behave.
Even for rich folks, this precept's full observance can't ever be very
costly. And, since you're not
very poor, you'll see clearly that, while it yields a strict judgment of
your conduct in The
Envelope case, it also yields a strict judgment of John's conduct in the
case of the Shallow Pond.
So, if we rely on this last precept as a guide for human conduct in the
two cases, the case of the
Shallow Pond and the case of The Envelope, aren't we then
committed to the view that a strict
judgment of your conduct in case of The Envelope is fully compatible
with a View that Ethics is
Highly Undemanding. from Peter Unger, "Living and Letting Die." Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996.
Louisiana Fishermen, USA

XXV. If John saves the child from drowning, he'll be saving,
actually
saving a child from dying; whereas in the case of The Envelope, if I
send
money, I will be only preventing children from dying.
So is this a difference between the two cases that might make a
moral difference or might help
to justify a more harsh judgment of John's conduct in the case of the
Shallow Pond and a more
lenient judgment of your tossing UNICEF's appeal into
the
wastebasket in the case of The
Envelope?
Changing format for a second the following handed out in class might
be of some (small) help:
Consider the following:
John is the driver of a trolley [remember this?], whose brakes have failed. On the track
ahead
of him are five people; the banks are so steep that they will not be
able to get
off the track in time. The track has a spur leading off to the right,
and John
can turn the trolley onto it. Unfortunately, there is one person on the
right
hand track. John can turn the trolley, killing the one; or he can
refrain from
turning the trolley. John elects to turn the trolley onto the right hand
track,
killing the one person.
John's trolley dilemma would appear to be fairly uncomplicated. It
would appear to
involve the weighing of the loss of five lives against the loss of just
one and whatever
weight we assign to the loss of a human life, it would appear that,
faced with one of two
alternatives, to choose the alternative where five die rather than the
alternative where
only one dies would do more harm than good. I say "it would
appear" because the two
alternatives are not, not quite, as I have laid them out. If John
chooses the latter
alternative over the former, he actually kills another human being,
whereas if he does not
turn the trolley he is letting five die. There may be only a small
difference in this
situation between killing and letting die, but generally we take it to
be a difference that
makes some moral difference. Does the moral difference between
killing and letting die
prompt you to give different weights to the alternatives John faces,
to assign, for
instance, a greater weight to the harm John would cause by turning
the trolley onto the
right hand track? Does the moral difference in this case between
killing and letting die
make enough of a difference to effect how the balance of relative
harms is struck?
2. Consider two variations on another hypothetical:
A. John hates Alice and wants her dead. John puts
cleaning fluid in Alice1s cocoa and Alice dies.
B. John hates Alice and wants her dead. Alice
inadvertently puts cleaning fluid in her cocoa, mistaking it
for liquid marshmellow fluff. John has the antidote to
cleaning fluid, but does not tell Alice. Alice dies.
In (A) John Kills Alice, but in (B) he merely lets her die. There does
not seem to be much to choose
between the two scenarios, however. John seems just as bad in (B)
as he is in (A), no?
Each of us is familiar of circumstances in the
law where
persons have a legal duty to refrain from performing certain actions
that will be harmful
to other persons and their property. So, for example, persons may
back their car into
the street from a driveway, but they have a legal duty to refrain
from stepping on the gas
when they see a small child in the rear-view mirror. Or I can use a
sharp knife to carve
the turkey, but I have a duty to refrain from plunging it into the
back of your neck. But
what are your moral intuitions about John's behaavior in (B) above?
Might there be
situations where omitting to do something for someone as opposed to
doing something to
her is a breach of duty?
CARE-Built Water System, Mozambique

back to top
XXVI. If I donate to UNICEF, I will be
spending my own money,
and my
money belongs to me and is something I am free to spend as I see fit
and I
should not be condemned for not giving to UNICEF something
that I
have a
right to in the first place.
Of course, it might be possible for John to claim something quite
similar in the case of the
Shallow Pond. He might say "My Gucci shoes belong to me and if
rescuing the child requires
that I get my shoes wet beyond repair and I elect to keep my feet
dry, that is my right and I
should not be faulted for refusing to destroy what I have a right to in
the first place: my Gucci
shoes. Property rights should count for something and I have a right
to my own property and I
should not be condemned for refusing to part with my property just
to save a child from
drowning." But leaving aside this retort from John, many of us
suspect that property rights do
count for something. Here's Singer on this score and although he is
not speaking directly to our
two cases he is trying to make sense of how property rights might
cause difficulties for his
views on our obligation to contribute to famine relief:
"Do people have a right to private property, a right that contradicts
the view that they are
under an obligation to give some of their wealth away to those in
absolute poverty? According
to some theories of rights (for instance, Robert Nozick's), provided
one has acquired one's
property without the use of unjust means like force and fraud, one
may be entitled to enormous
wealth while others starve. This individualistic conception of rights
is in contrast to other
views, like the early Christian doctrine to be found in the works of
Thomas Aquinas, which
holds that since property exists for the satisfaction of human needs,
'whatever a man has in
superabundance is owed, of natural right to the poor for their
sustenance'. A socialist would
also, of course, see wealth as belonging to the community rather than
the individual, while
utilitarians, whether socialist or not, would be prepared to override
property rights to prevent
great evils.
"Does the argument for an obligation to assist others, therefore,
presuppose one of these other
theories of property rights, and not an individualistic theory like
Nozick's? Not necessarily.
A theory of property rights can insist on our right to retain wealth
without pronouncing on
whether the rich ought to give to the poor. Nozick, for example,
rejects the use of compulsory
means like taxation to redistribute income, but suggests that we can
achieve the ends we deem
morally desirable by voluntary means. So Nozick would reject the
claim that rich people have
an 'obligation' to give to the poor, in so far as this implies that the
poor have a right to our aid,
but might accept that giving is something we ought to do and failing
to give, though within
one's rights, is wrong-for there is more to an ethical life than
respecting the rights of others.
"The argument for an obligation to assist can survive, with only
minor modifications, even if we
accept an individualistic theory of property rights. In any case,
however, I do not think we
should accept such a theory. It leaves too much to chance to be an
acceptable ethical view. For
instance, those whose forefathers happened to inhabit some sandy
wastes around the Persian
Gulf are now fabulously wealthy, because oil lay under those sands;
while those whose
forefathers settled on better land south of the Sahara live in absolute
poverty, because of
drought and bad harvests. Can this distribution be acceptable from
an impartial point of view?
If we imagine ourselves about to begin life as a citizen of either
Bahrein or Chad, but we do not
know which, would we accept the principle that, citizens of Bahrein
are under no obligation to
assist people living in Chad?" - Peter Singer, "Practical Ethics." Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979.

back to top
Photo Credits: Courtesy of Oxfam America and
CARE
See also Peter Singer, "Famine, Affluence and Morality" in the Perry and Bratman TEXT
Full text of SINGER'S "FAMINE, AFFLUENCE, AND MORALITY" Online (Brandeis Access Only).
Originally published in The Philosophical Review, Vol. 76, No. 4. (Oct., 1967), pp. 460-475.
Also Singer's "SOLUTION TO WORLD POVERTY", which appeared in The New York Times Sunday Magazine on September 5, 1999 is available HERE..
OPTIONAL LINKS
Hugh LaFollette and Larry May, "Suffer the Little Children" in World Hunger and Morality ed. William Aiken and Hugh LaFollette Prentice-Hall, Inc. 1996
Garrett Hardin, "Life Boat Ethics The Case Against Helping the Poor"
Psychology Today September 1974, pp.38-43, 124-126.
William Aiken, "The 'Carrying Capacity' Equivocation: A Reply to Garrett Hardin,"
Social Theory and Practice, v.6(1), Spring 1980, pp.1-11.
A Visual Display from Paris "Six Billion Human Beings"
Charles Mann, "How Many Is Too Many?", The Atlantic Monthly, February 1993
Mark Sagoff, "Do We Consume Too Much?" The Atlantic Monthly, June 1997
Bill McKibben, "A Special Moment in History," The Atlantic Monthly, May 1998
Amartya Sen, "Population: Delusion and Reality,"September 22, 1994 from his lecture before the United Nations on April 18, 1994
Amartya Sen, "Public Action to Remedy Hunger," The Tanco Memorial Lecture, August 2, 1990. London.
Amartya Sen, "Hunger: Old Torments and New Blunders," The Little Magazine,Vol II: Issue 6.
[PHIL 1A]
[Syllabus]
[Handouts]
[Home]
[Bio]
[CV]
[PHIL DEPT.]
[E-MAIL]
Send comments to: Andreas Teuberr
URL: http://phils7.dce.harvard.edu/
Last Modified: 03/26/02
Instructor's Toolkit
Copyright © The President and Fellows of Harvard College
|